ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1879
PRE-EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES: HOW
PREDISPOSITION CONTRACTS COULD BE THE
WINNING SOLUTION
Ashley Alenick
TABLE OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION .............................................................................................................. 1880
I. B
ACKGROUND ......................................................................................................... 1883
A. In Vitro Fertilization ................................................................................. 1883
B. Courts in the United States Have Three Main Approaches for
Resolving Dispositional Disputes About Frozen Pre-Embryos in the
Context of a Divorce Proceeding .............................................................. 1884
II. T
HE PREDISPOSITION CONTRACT IS THE BEST OF THE THREE JUDICIAL
APPROACHES, BUT RAISES SOME CONCERNS ABOUT PROCEDURAL AND
SUBSTANTIVE FAIRNESS ......................................................................................... 1889
III. T
HE PREDISPOSITION APPROACH SHOULD BE HONED WITH REFERENCE TO
THE
PARADIGM OF PRENUPTIAL AND SURROGACY AGREEMENTS ..................... 1894
A. Both Prenuptial and Surrogacy Agreements Are Analogous to the
Predisposition Contract ............................................................................. 1895
1. The Prenuptial and Predisposition Agreements Are
Historically, Conceptually, and Generically Similar ................. 1895
a. Similarities in History Reveal that Predisposition
and Prenuptial Agreements Further the Same Public
Policies, such that the Latter May Be a Logical
Paradigm for Implementing the Former ........................ 1895
b. Prenuptial and Predisposition Agreements Are
Fundamentally Similar in Concept, Suggesting that
Associate Editor, Cardozo Law Review, Volume 38. J.D. Candidate (June 2017), Benjamin
N. Cardozo School of Law; B.A. New York University, 2013. I would like to thank Professor
Peter Goodrich for his advice as my Note advisor. I would also like to express my gratitude to
all of the Cardozo Law Review editors for their hard work in making the publication of this
Note a reality. Most importantly, thank you to my family for your endless support and
encouragement during this process, as well as throughout law school and beyond.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1880 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
the Former Could Be a Paradigm for the Latter ............ 1896
c. Generic Similarities Further Support the Proposition
that Prenuptial Contracts May Be Models for
Predisposition Agreements .............................................. 1897
2. Predisposition Contracts Can Gain Force from Surrogacy
Agreements, Another Type of Ante-Natal Contract Whose
Enforcement Is Predicated upon Procedural and
Substantive Fairness ...................................................................... 1899
B. Safeguards to Assure Procedural Fairness in the Realm of
Prenuptial and Surrogacy Agreements Would Also Address the
Concerns About Predisposition Contracts Pertaining to Frozen Pre-
Embryos ....................................................................................................... 1901
1. Procedural Fairness in the Context of Prenuptial
Agreements Requires Voluntariness and Full Disclosure of
Finances .......................................................................................... 1902
2. Surrogacy Contracts Are Procedurally Fair if the Parties
Have Had the Opportunity to Seek Independent Counsel,
Compensation Is Reasonable, and the Gestator Has the
Right to Rescind Following Delivery .......................................... 1904
C. Substantive Fairness Protections as Applied to Prenuptial and
Surrogacy Agreements Could, Likewise, Pertain to Predisposition
Contracts ..................................................................................................... 1907
1. Substantive Fairness in the Realm of Prenuptial
Agreements Focuses on Unforeseen Developments that
Would Cause Hardship ................................................................ 1907
2. The Ramifications of Intervening Events Are Likewise a
Key Factor for Courts in Determining Whether a Surrogacy
Contract Is Substantively Fair ...................................................... 1909
IV. P
ROPOSAL ................................................................................................................ 1910
A. Predisposition Contracts Should Be Separate from Informed
Consent Forms to Assure Procedural Fairness ....................................... 1910
B. Predisposition Contracts Should Consider Biological Realities to
Assure Substantive Fairness ...................................................................... 1913
C
ONCLUSION................................................................................................................... 1914
I
NTRODUCTION
Starting a family through pregnancy is not always easy. For some,
conceiving a child is a daunting medical odyssey punctuated by
reproductive assistance after attempts at natural conception prove
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1881
unsuccessful. In vitro fertilization (IVF)
1
is one such method of medical
reproductive assistance that has greatly assisted couples struggling with
procreation.
2
Yet, this medical process is not without legal
complications.
Such complications arise because IVF not only provides a means
for achieving pregnancy in the present, but also includes the potential
for doing so in the future through the use of pre-embryos that are frozen
for implantation at a later time.
3
The legal issues arise when a couple has
opted to divorce,
4
and disagree about the disposition of the frozen pre-
embryos that remain following IVF. For example, one party may want
the frozen pre-embryos for future implantation whereas another may
prefer to have them donated for research.
5
The courts are not united in
their approaches for deciding such disputes.
6
1
IVF, the most effective form of assisted reproductive technology, “is a complex series of
procedures used to treat fertility or genetic problems and assist with the conception of a child.
During IVF, mature eggs are collected (retrieved) from [a woman’s] ovaries and fertilized by
sperm in a lab.” In Vitro Fertilization (IVF): Overview, M
AYO CLINIC, http://
www.mayoclinic.org/tests-procedures/in-vitro-fertilization/basics/definition/prc-20018905 (last
visited Jan. 7, 2016). The fertilized eggs are then implanted into a woman’s uterus, either that of
the intended mother or a gestational carrier. Id.
2
Since being introduced in the United States in 1981, IVF has resulted in more than
200,000 babies. Infertility and In Vitro Fertilization, W
EBMD, http://www.webmd.com/
infertility-and-reproduction/guide/in-vitro-fertilization (last visited Sept. 7, 2015).
3
“Extra embryos can be frozen and stored for future use for several years. Not all embryos
will survive the freezing and thawing process, although most will. Cryopreservation can make
future cycles of IVF less expensive and less invasive.” In Vitro Fertilization (IVF): How You
Prepare, M
AYO CLINIC, http://www.mayoclinic.org/tests-procedures/in-vitro-fertilization/
basics/how-you-prepare/prc-20018905 (last visited Jan. 7, 2016).
4
Similar issues may also arise where a couple that is not married differs as to the
disposition of frozen pre-embryos at the conclusion of the relationship. This Note considers the
issue only in the context of a married couple that has opted to divorce, has a pre-disposition
contract, and has asked the court to decide how to dispose of frozen pre-embryos that remain
following IVF.
5
See Helene S. Shapo, Frozen Pre-Embryos and the Right to Change One’s Mind, 12 DUKE
J. COMP. & INTL L. 75, 80 (2002) (“The choices include destroying the pre-embryos, giving
them to the clinic for research, donating them to another couple, and releasing them to one of
the parties.”).
6
As described at greater length in Section I.B., infra, the first such approach is a
constitutional analysis through which the court determines the fate of pre-embryos by
balancing one party’s right to procreate against the other’s right not to. See, e.g., Davis v. Davis,
842 S.W.2d 588 (Tenn. 1992). The second approach requires the contemporaneous agreement
of the parties, pending which agreement the court maintains the status quo and directs that the
pre-embryos remain frozen. See, e.g., Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶¶ 27
31. Under the third approach, the court enforces a contract into which the parties entered at the
time of IVF, in which they provide for the disposition of pre-embryos in the event of divorce.
See, e.g., Kass v. Kass, 91 N.Y.2d 554 (1998).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1882 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
Judicial cacophony in this area is troubling given the reality that
both IVF and divorce are fairly commonplace in the United States.
7
The
issue as to which of the divorcing spouses will receive possession of the
frozen pre-embryos, therefore, is a recurring one.
8
Having a uniform
legal standard is important to the efficient and effective resolution of
this enduring concern. What is impeding the path toward a single
cognizable judicial standard?
The complication may lie in the nature of frozen pre-embryos
themselves because they evoke many difficult and debatable
considerations. For example, frozen pre-embryos represent potential
life, thereby implicating religious beliefs.
9
They delve into the realm of
procreation, prompting discussion about privacy rights.
10
They could be
viewed as a species of property, thus occasioning debate as to the policy
implications of such a characterization.
11
These thought-provoking
issues may be at the core of why the courts have yet to establish a
uniform legal standard for disposing of frozen pre-embryos despite the
compelling need for one.
This judicial dilemma is entirely avoidable through the use of a
predisposition contract that adopts the standards required to enforce
similar ante-natal arrangements. More specifically, this Note posits that
disputes about the disposition of frozen pre-embryos should be decided
based upon a contract between the divorcing spouses entered into
before IVF that comports with the procedural and substantive fairness
standards for enforcing both a prenuptial and surrogacy agreement.
This Note proceeds in four parts. Part I discusses the background
of IVF and provides further detail about the three approaches courts
presently use to award frozen pre-embryos in a divorce proceeding. Part
II suggests that a predisposition contract
12
is the preferred model, albeit
7
See, e.g., Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 557; see also Marriage & Divorce, AM. PSYCHOL. ASSN, http://
www.apa.org/topics/divorce (last visited Jan. 7, 2016) (noting that forty to fifty percent of
married couples in the United States divorce).
8
“It has been estimated that tens of thousands of pre-embryos are frozen each year,” thus
enhancing the possibility that disposition could become an issue for resolution in divorce
proceedings. See Shapo, supra note 5, at 76.
9
See, e.g., Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 594 ([“T]he trial judge concluded that the eight-cell entities
at issue were not pre[-]embryos but were ‘children in vitro.’”).
10
Id. at 598 (“We conclude that the answer to this dilemma [whether the parties will
become parents] turns on the parties’ exercise of their constitutional right to privacy.”).
11
Id. at 596 (stating that “the Court of Appeals has left the implication that [the parties’
interest in pre-embryos] is in the nature of a property interest” and concluding “that this point
must be further addressed”); see also Bridget M. Fuselier, The Trouble with Putting All of Your
Eggs in One Basket: Using a Property Rights Model to Resolve Disputes over Cryopreserved Pre-
Embryos, 14 T
EX. J. ON C.L. & C.R. 143 (2009).
12
Predisposition contracts “provide a scheme for the disposition of frozen embryos in the
event of contingencies, such as divorce.” Noel A. Fleming, Navigating the Slippery Slope of
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1883
with some concerns about procedural and substantive fairness. Part III
compares predisposition contracts with prenuptial and surrogacy
agreements, and argues that the heightened standards for assuring that
the latter two are both procedurally and substantively fair should also
apply when enforcing the former. Finally, Part IV applies the paradigm
for implementing prenuptial and surrogacy contracts to predisposition
agreements, and proposes that courts enforce the latter only if separate
from any medical consent form, voluntarily made, and based upon full
disclosure so as to assure procedural fairness. Part IV further proposes
that courts consider whether enforcement of a predisposition contract
would result in one of the parties being unable to achieve genetic
parenthood as the test for determining substantive fairness.
I.
BACKGROUND
A. In Vitro Fertilization
IVF involves the removal of ova
13
from a woman,
14
fertilization of
the ova in a petri dish using sperm provided from a man, and
transferring the product of this process into the uterus of a woman.
15
As
more fully explained in Kass v. Kass,
16
the IVF procedure begins with
hormonal stimulation of a woman’s ovaries so as to yield multiple
eggs.
17
These eggs are removed by laparoscopy
18
and fused with the
sperm to create a pre-zygote.
19
The pre-zygotes divide, becoming a pre-
Frozen Embryo Disputes: The Case for a Contractual Approach, 75 TEMP. L. REV. 345, 370
(2002).
13
Ova is the plural of ovum, defined as “the female reproductive cell . . . which is capable of
developing, usually only after fertilization, into a new individual.” Ovum, D
ICTIONARY.COM,
http://www.dictionary.com/browse/ova (last visited Jan. 9, 2017).
14
This Note assumes that the woman and man are husband and wife, however the analysis
provided could also apply to same-sex married couples who had frozen embryos and are
seeking divorce, as well as to unmarried couples ending their relationship.
15
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 591.
16
Kass v. Kass, 91 N.Y.2d 554, 55758 (1998).
17
The fertility hormone used to increase the number of produced ova is gonadotropin.
IVFWhat Is In Vitro Fertilisation (IVF) and How Does It Work?, H
UM. FERTILISATION &
EMBRYOLOGY AUTHORITY, http://www.hfea.gov.uk/IVF.html (last visited Jan. 7, 2016)
[hereinafter H
UM. FERTILISATION & EMBRYOLOGY AUTHORITY].
18
Laparoscopy is a “type of surgery in which small incisions are made in the abdominal
wall through which a laparoscope and other instruments can be placed to permit structures
within the abdomen and pelvis to be seen.” See Medical Definition of Laparoscopy,
M
EDICINENET.COM, http://www.medicinenet.com/script/main/art.asp?articlekey=6211 (last
updated May 13, 2016).
19
See HUM. FERTILISATION & EMBRYOLOGY AUTHORITY, supra note 17. More specifically,
the eggs are collected using ultrasound guidance, mixed with the sperm, and cultured in the
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1884 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
embryo,
20
and after reaching the four- to eight-cell stage, are transferred
to the woman’s uterus by cervical catheter.
21
The hope is that the pre-
embryo will attach to the uterine wall and develop into a fetus.
22
Although multiple eggs are implanted during the IVF procedure,
the total removed from the woman may exceed the number that are
transferred back as pre-embryos.
23
The remaining pre-embryos may be
cryopreservedfrozen in liquid nitrogen for later use.
24
Because cryopreservation can sustain pre-embryos for many years,
intervening circumstances, including divorce, can arise and lead to
disagreement about disposition of the remaining organisms.
25
To date,
courts have adopted three approaches for resolving these disputes.
26
B. Courts in the United States Have Three Main Approaches for
Resolving Dispositional Disputes About Frozen Pre-Embryos in the
Context of a Divorce Proceeding
Courts in the United States are not united in their approach for
resolving disputes about frozen pre-embryos when the spouses who
laboratory for sixteen to twenty hours after which point they are checked for signs of
fertilization. Id.
20
Gametes are the sexual reproductive cells (egg and sperm) that unite to form a pre-
zygote. See Gamete, D
ICTIONARY.COM, http://www.dictionary.com/browse/gamete (last visited
Jan. 9, 2017). More specifically, pre-zygotes are “eggs which have been penetrated by sperm but
have not yet joined genetic material.” Litowitz v. Litowitz, 48 P.3d 261, 524 n.51 (Wash. 2002)
(en banc) (quoting Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 557 n.1). A pre-embryo is defined as “that stage in
human development immediately after fertilization occurs. The pre[-]embryo ‘comes into
existence with the first cell division and lasts until the appearance of a single primitive streak,
which is the first sign of organ differentiation. This [primitive streak] occurs at about fourteen
days of development.’” Id. at 262 n.2 (second alteration in original) (quoting Donna A. Katz,
Article, My Egg, Your Sperm, Whose Preembryo? A Proposal for Deciding Which Party Receives
Custody of Frozen Preembryos, 5 V
A. J. SOC. POLY & L. 623, 62829 n.42 (1998)). Courts use the
terms “pre-zygote” and “pre-embryo” interchangeably, despite the distinctions in definition.
21
Id. at 262 n.8. An embryologist monitors the development of the embryos so that the best
ones will be chosen for transfer. H
UM. FERTILISATION & EMBRYOLOGY AUTHORITY, supra note
17.
22
Litowitz, 48 P.3d at 262 n.8.
23
HUM. FERTILISATION & EMBRYOLOGY AUTHORITY, supra note 17. One or two pre-
embryos are transferred to a woman under the age of forty; a maximum of three pre-embryos
are transferred to those forty and older. “The number of embryos transferred is restricted
because of the risks associated with multiple births.Id.
24
“Cryopreservation serves to reduce both medical and physical costs because eggs do not
have to be retrieved with each attempted implantation, and delay may actually improve the
chances of pregnancy.” Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 557.
25
See, e.g., Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 28; J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d
707, 716 (N.J. 2001); Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 558; Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 591 (Tenn. 1992).
26
See Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 16 (observing that courts have “generally
conducted three types of analyses” to determine disposition of pre-embryos in a divorce
proceeding).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1885
created them have decided to end their marriage.
27
The legal framework
for determining to whom the pre-embryos should be awarded divides
into three types of analyses.
28
Courts adopt either a constitutional
analysis,
29
a contemporaneous agreement approach,
30
or enforce a
contract into which the parties entered immediately prior to IVF that
includes a provision about disposition of the unused pre-embryos in the
event of divorce.
31
Under the constitutional analysis, the issue of disposition is framed
in terms of a balancing test of procreational interests that derives from
the protection of privacy as embedded in both state and federal
constitutions.
32
Though not expressly provided, the right to privacy is
inherent in the constitutional concept of liberty,
33
and includes the right
to procreate as well as the concomitant right to not.
34
Because the
disposition issue arises prior to the implantation of the pre-embryo, the
concerns about a woman’s bodily integrity that exist in the context of
abortion cases are not implicated, and the spouses are viewed as equal
providers.
35
A great tension arises when one spouse wishes to exercise
the right to procreate while the other wishes to exercise their right not
27
See supra note 6.
28
See Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 16 (“Courts in other jurisdictions [that] have
addressed the issue [of cryopreserved pre-embryos] generally conducted three types of analyses
in resolving this question: (1) a contractual approach; (2) a contemporaneous mutual consent
approach; and/or (3) a balancing approach.”). More specifically, the contractual approach has
been adopted in five states. See id. 20; see also Dahl v. Angle, 194 P.3d 834, 84041 (Or. Ct.
App. 2008); Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 597; Roman v. Roman, 193 S.W.3d 40, 50 (Tex. App. 2006);
Litowitz v. Litowitz, 48 P.3d 261 (Wash. 2002) (en banc). Iowa and Missouri have adopted the
contemporaneous mutual consent approach. See Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 30; see
also Gadberry v. Gadberry, No. 13SL-DR06185, at *911 (Mo. Cir. Ct. Apr. 13, 2015), aff’d sub
nom. McQueen v. Gadberry, 507 S.W.3d 127 (Mo. Ct. App. 2016). The balancing approach has
been adopted in New Jersey, Pennsylvania, and Tennessee. See Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st)
122975, ¶¶ 29, 3336.
29
See, e.g., Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 603; see also supra note 6.
30
See, e.g., Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 41.
31
See, e.g., Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 557.
32
See Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604 (balancing husband’s “interest in avoiding parenthood
[against wife’s] interest in donating the pre[-]embryos to another couple for implantation”).
33
Id. at 59899.
34
Id. at 60001. “[P]rocreational autonomy is composed of two rights of equal
significancethe right to procreate and the right to avoid procreation.” Id. at 601.
35
Spouses “must be seen as entirely equivalent gamete-providers.” Id. But see Planned
Parenthood of Cent. Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U.S. 52, 71 (1976) (discussing abortion and stating
that “[i]nasmuch as it is the woman who physically bears the child and who is the more directly
and immediately affected by the pregnancy, as between the two, the balance weighs in her
favor”).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1886 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
to.
36
The constitutional analysis balances these interests in the context of
a dispute about pre-embryos remaining at the time of divorce.
37
The New Jersey Supreme Court applied the constitutional
approach in J.B. v. M.B,
38
where, in a divorce proceeding, the wife
wanted to destroy the frozen pre-embryos and the husband wanted
them donated to infertile couples.
39
Specifically, the court found that the
husband’s constitutional right to procreate would not be forfeited if the
pre-embryos were not donated, whereas the wife’s constitutional right
not to procreate would be forever lost if the pre-embryos were used in
any way.
40
Thus, the court ordered the pre-embryos be destroyed.
41
The contemporaneous approach posits a different view. Rather
than balance interests, courts applying this approach insist on
unanimous agreement.
42
If either spouse has had a change of mind
about the disposition agreement made at the time of IVF, that person’s
current objection takes precedence.
43
When a couple is unable to concur
on the disposition at the time of divorce, under the contemporaneous
approach, the court directs that the pre-embryos remain in storage until
such time a joint decision is reached.
44
Iowa’s Supreme Court applied the contemporaneous approach in
In re Marriage of Witten,
45
a case where the wife sought to use the pre-
36
“The equivalence of and inherent tension between these two interests are nowhere more
evident than in the context of in vitro fertilization.” Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 601.
37
See J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 716 (N.J. 2001) (stating that precedents on the right to
privacy in the context of procreational rights “provide a framework within which disputes over
the disposition of pre[-]embryos can be resolved”); see also Michelle F. Sublett, Note, Frozen
Embryos: What Are They and How Should the Law Treat Them, 38 C
LEV. ST. L. REV. 585 (1990)
(discussing the basis and development of the constitutional right to make individual decisions
about reproduction).
38
See J.B., 783 A.2d 707.
39
Id. at 710.
40
Id. at 717 (refusing to force the wife to become a biological parent against her will).
41
Id. at 720.
42
Specifically, the contemporaneous approach holds that “no embryo should be used by
either partner, donated to another patient, used in research, or destroyed without the
[contemporaneous] mutual consent of the couple that created the embryo.” In re Marriage of
Witten, 672 N.W.2d 768, 778 (Iowa 2003) (quoting Carl H. Coleman, Procreative Liberty and
Contemporaneous Choice: An Inalienable Rights Approach to Frozen Embryo Disputes, 84
MINN. L. REV. 55, 110 (1999)); Gadberry v. Gadberry, No. 13SL-DR06185, at *11 (Mo. Cir. Ct.
Apr. 13, 2015), aff’d sub nom. McQueen v. Gadberry, 507 S.W.3d 127 (Mo. Ct. App. 2016); cf.
J.B., 783 A.2d 707.
43
See Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶¶ 2628; Gadberry, No. 13SL-
DR06185, at *1011.
44
Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 28 (“Unlike the other possible disposition
decisionsuse by one partner, donation to another patient, donation to research, or
destructionkeeping the embryos frozen is not final and irrevocable. By preserving the status
quo, it makes it possible for the partners to reach an agreement at a later time.” (quoting
Witten, 672 N.W.2d at 778)).
45
672 N.W.2d 768.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1887
embryos for future implantation over the objection of the husband who
sought an injunction prohibiting either party from using them without
both their written consents.
46
The court sided with the husband upon
concluding that the contemporaneous approach was the best of the
three options.
47
The third approach for resolving these disputes relies upon a
contract set forth in a consent form that the spouses sign prior to IVF
containing a provision for the disposition of the pre-embryos in the
event of divorce.
48
Some jurisdictions recognize an exception to the
contract approach where one of the parties is unable to achieve
parenthood other than through use of the frozen pre-embryos.
49
This third approach is the one courts most often apply, perhaps
most famously so in Davis v. Davis.
50
Though the spouses in Davis had
no predisposition contract governing the unused pre-embryos, the
Tennessee Supreme Court expressly addressed the enforceability of
prior agreements, stating that such arrangements should be
determinative.
51
46
Id. at 77273.
47
Specifically, the court rejected the contract approach upon finding that “it would be
against the public policy of this state to enforce a prior agreement between the parties in this
highly personal area of reproductive choice when one of the parties has changed his or her
mind concerning the disposition or use of the embryos.Id. at 781. Similarly, the court rejected
the constitutional approach based on “the grave public policy concerns we have with the
balancing test, which simply substitutes the court as decision maker.” Id. at 783; see also
Gadberry, No. 13SL-DR06185, at *13 (awarding the frozen pre-embryos jointly “due to the
special character of this marital property,” and prohibiting either divorcing spouse from
transferring, releasing, or using them without the signed authorization of the other).
48
See, e.g., Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶¶ 4–6; see also Kass v. Kass, 91 N.Y.2d
554, 565 (1998) (“Agreements between progenitors, or gamete donors, regarding disposition of
their pre-zygotes should generally be presumed valid and binding, and enforced in any dispute
between them.” (citing Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 597 (Tenn. 1992))); Dahl v. Angle, 194
P.3d 834, 840 (Or. Ct. App. 2008) (concluding that “the general framework set forth by the
courts in Davis and Kass, in which courts give effect to the progenitors’ intent by enforcing the
progenitors’ advance directive regarding the embryos, is persuasive”); Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 597;
Roman v. Roman, 193 S.W.3d 40, 50 (Tex. App. 2006) (“[A]llowing the parties voluntarily to
decide the disposition of frozen embryos in advance of cryopreservation, subject to mutual
change of mind, jointly expressed, best serves the existing public policy of this State and the
interests of the parties.”); Litowitz v. Litowitz, 48 P.3d 261, 268 (Wash. 2002) (en banc)
(enforcing the predisposition contract on which both parties rely “in asserting their rights”).
49
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604 (noting, without further analysis, that “[t]he case would be
closer if Mary Sue Davis were seeking to use the pre[-]embryos herself, but only if she could not
achieve parenthood by any other reasonable means”). This Note posits that, in such a case,
enforcing the predisposition contract would be substantively unfair. See infra Section IV.B.
50
842 S.W.2d 588.
51
The court specifically stated in what has become influential dicta that predisposition
agreements must be enforced
in order to provide the necessary guidance to all those involved with IVF procedures
in Tennessee in the future—the health care professionals who administer IVF
programs and the scientists who engage in infertility research, as well as prospective
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1888 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
In Kass v. Kass,
52
the New York Court of Appeals also applied the
predisposition contract approach. In Kass, the husband and wife
underwent IVF, as a result of which five pre-embryos were
cryopreserved.
53
Prior to implantation, the husband and wife signed a
consent form pursuant to which they directed that, in the event of
divorce, the IVF program would keep any unused frozen pre-embryos
for research.
54
Notwithstanding the consent form, the wife requested
sole custody of the pre-embryos at the time of the parties’ divorce so
that she could undergo another round of IVF.
55
In denying the wife’s
request, the court was persuaded by the parties’ clear intention set forth
in their predisposition agreement.
56
The court respected and enforced
this intent based on its belief that the spouses should be the sole
decision-makers as to this quintessentially personal issue.
57
parents seeking to achieve pregnancy by means of IVF, their physicians, and their
counselors.
Id. at 597. The court proceeded to state that it
believe[s], as a starting point, that an agreement regarding disposition of any
untransferred pre[-]embryos in the event of contingencies (such as . . . divorce . . . )
should be presumed valid and should be enforced as between the progenitors. This
conclusion is in keeping with the proposition that the progenitors, having provided
the gametic material giving rise to the pre[-]embryos, retain decision-making
authority as to their disposition.
Id.; accord Litowitz, 48 P.3d at 267 (recognizing that the Tennessee Supreme court “has wisely
observed” that disputes involving disposition of pre-embryos should be resolved based upon a
prior directive contract).
52
91 N.Y.2d 554.
53
Id. at 560.
54
Id. at 55960.
55
Id. at 560.
56
Specifically, the couple wanted to avoid a “stranger taking [the] decision out of their
hands.” Id. at 567 (“The conclusion that emerges most strikingly from reviewing these consents
as a whole is that appellant and respondent intended that disposition of the pre-zygotes was to
be their joint decision. . . . Even in unforeseen circumstances, even if they were unavailable,
even if they were dead, the consents jointly specified the disposition that would be made.”).
57
“To the extent possible, it should be the progenitorsnot the State and not the courts
who by their prior directive make this deeply personal life choice.” Id. at 566. J.B. v. M.B. is
another case where the court opined on the value of pre-embryo disposition agreements despite
the absence of one in the case presented. Citing to both Kass and Davis, the New Jersey
Supreme Court in J.B. acknowledged the value of the reasoning behind the enforcement of
predisposition contracts. J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 719 (N.J. 2001).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1889
II. THE PREDISPOSITION CONTRACT IS THE BEST OF THE THREE
JUDICIAL APPROACHES, BUT RAISES SOME CONCERNS ABOUT PROCEDURAL
AND SUBSTANTIVE FAIRNESS
This Note’s proposal that courts deciding disputes about frozen
pre-embryos should enforce a predisposition contract is grounded in
the premise that such agreements are the best of the three approaches.
58
As the court aptly observed in Kass, explicit agreements are useful in the
commercial context to avoid the costs of litigation.
59
Their value is even
greater in the noncommercial context of a fertility arrangement where
the emotional costs are enormous.
60
Added to this benefit is the value of
permitting the spouses themselves to make the uniquely personal
decisions pertaining to their assisted reproductive treatments.
61
Advance directives also afford a degree of certainty to the medical
provider, which thereby facilitates the effective operation of their IVF
programs.
62
Thus, a key attribute of the predisposition approach is the
furtherance of parenthood by both supporting those who provide
assisted reproductive therapy and those who seek it.
The constitutional approach, by contrast, provides far less support
in this regard because it is grounded in a misguided definition of
parenthood.
63
Indeed, the balancing test that is the cornerstone of the
constitutional approach assumes that parenthood is defined by genetics
58
See Ceala E. Breen-Portnoy, Comment, Frozen Embryo Disposition in Cases of Separation
and Divorce: How Nahmani v. Nahmani and Davis v. Davis Form the Foundation for a
Workable Expansion of Current International Family Planning Regimes, 28 M
D. J. INTL L. 275,
292 (2013) (“In case of separation or divorce, [a] written agreement would ideally help avoid
many of the issues the courts see today.”); see also Fleming, supra note 12, at 371 (“Enforcing
disposition contracts with clear, specific language is the most efficient and judicious way of
resolving conflicts that arise between parties concerning the disposition of their frozen
embryos.”).
59
See Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 565 (acknowledging the value of explicit agreements in a
commercial context).
60
Id. (recognizing that explicit agreements “are all the more necessary and desirable in
personal matters of reproductive choice, where the intangible costs of any litigation are simply
incalculable”).
61
Additionally, predisposition agreements maximize reproductive freedom “by reserving to
the progenitors the authority to make what is in the first instance a quintessentially personal,
private decision.” Id.; see also Fleming, supra note 12, at 372 (“Freedom to contract enhances
liberty, even if in the future such agreements impose constraints that one or both parties had
wished to avoid.”).
62
Fleming, supra note 12, at 372 (“[C]ourts should uphold contracts for the disposition of
frozen embryos because this will provide IVF clinics with certainty as to how they can store and
dispose of embryos.”); see also Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 597 (Tenn. 1992) (addressing
the importance of pre-disposition contracts as giving guidance to “the health care professionals
who administer IVF programs and the scientists who engage in infertility research”).
63
Angela K. Upchurch, The Deep Freeze: A Critical Examination of the Resolution of Frozen
Embryo Disputes Through the Adversarial Process, 33 F
LA. ST. U. L. REV. 395, 423 (2005).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1890 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
alone when weighing the parties’ competing interests in procreating or
not.
64
Such a myopic notion of parenthood is at odds with the definition
applied in custody disputes where the court considers the closeness of
the relationship that develops between offspring and a mother or father
to determine the best interests of the child.
65
Moreover, if biology alone
determined parenthood, then support proceedings against genetic
parents would be unnecessary.
66
Yet these proceedings are routinely
brought in instances where a mere genetic connection is insufficient to
prompt financial support on a voluntary basis.
67
The constitutional approach is also problematic in its mechanical
application. With one lone exception,
68
the cases in which courts apply
this approach regularly favor the progenitor who does not want
implantation.
69
The Davis court
70
actually held that the spouse seeking
not to procreate ordinarily should prevail in a divorce dispute about the
disposition of frozen pre-embryos unless the other spouse has no other
64
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 603 (stating that becoming parents in the genetic sense would have
a “profound impact” on the gamete-providers).
65
See, e.g., Barstad v. Barstad, 499 N.W.2d 584, 58889 (N.D. 1993) (determining that the
best interest standard is met by permitting the mother to remain custodial parent because her
continuous and uninterrupted relationship with her son “has been important to [Ryan’s]
development as a happy, well-adjusted child” (citation omitted)). But see Sublett, supra note 37,
at 604 (noting that the factors comprising the best interest test “[c]learly . . . do not apply to
frozen embryos which are not developed enough to have brain activity, let alone wishes or
relationships with others”).
66
Upchurch, supra note 63, at 42324.
67
Id. at 424.
68
See Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131 (Pa. Super. Ct. 2012). In Reber, the husband and the wife
underwent IVF to preserve her ability to conceive a child in light of the chemotherapy she was
to undergo that was expected to hinder her fertility. Id. at 1132. Shortly after the IVF procedure
was completed, the husband filed for divorce and had a biological child with another woman.
Id. at 1133. In the divorce proceeding, the trial court awarded the frozen pre-embryos to the
wife upon finding that her interests in procreating outweighed the husband’s interests to the
contrary. Id. at 1134. In ruling for the wife, the Reber court expressly disagreed with the
decision in Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604, holding that the possibility of adoption is sufficient to
defeat the interest of the progenitor seeking to use the embryos to procreate. Reber, 42 A.3d at
1138 (“There is no question that the ability to have a biological child and/or be pregnant is a
distinct experience from adoption. Thus, simply because adoption or foster parenting may be
available to Wife, it does not mean that such options should be given equal weight in a
balancing test.”). Notably, the wife testified that she would permit the husband to participate in
raising any child born from the pre-embryos if he wanted that opportunity, and even then
would not expect any financial support from him. Id. at 1140. On these extreme facts, the
appellate court agreed that the balance of interests favored the wife, and sustained the award of
pre-embryos. Id. at 1142; cf. Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, 37 (refusing to
apply Reber despite the wife’s infertility following chemotherapy and, instead, holding that the
parties’ prior agreement is the best approach for resolving pre-embryo disputes).
69
But see Reber, 42 A.3d 1131.
70
Because of the absence of a predisposition agreement in Davis, the court applied the
constitutional approach to decide the case. Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 598.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1891
“reasonable possibility” of becoming a parent.
71
“Reasonable possibility”
is broadly defined to include both a willingness to undergo further IVF
procedures or to adopt.
72
Thus, the constitutional approach is faulty as
being fully skewed against the spouse seeking to procreate.
The contemporaneous approach is also flawed. Fundamentally, this
approach is unworkable
73
in a divorce proceeding where, by definition,
the parties have been unable to reach a present agreement about the
disposition of a pre-embryo and, thus, have sought judicial intervention.
Moreover, the contemporaneous approach is practically unsound.
Rather than promote agreement, it effectively fuels the existing
dissension in a divorce proceeding by conferring upon each party the
unilateral power to prevent use of the pre-embryos
74
and, thereby, to
void a previous disposition agreement that was knowingly and fairly
made. Accordingly, this approach is subject to further criticism as one
that undermines consent
75
and contravenes pacta sunt servanda.
76
Thus,
71
“Ordinarily, the party wishing to avoid procreation should prevail, assuming that the
other party has a reasonable possibility of achieving parenthood by means other than use of the
pre[-]embryos in question.” Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604; accord J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 716
(N.J. 2001) (agreeing “with the Tennessee Supreme Court that ‘[o]rdinarily, the party wishing
to avoid procreation should prevail’” (citing Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604)).
72
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604; see also J.B., 783 A.2d at 717 (observing that the right to
procreate is not lost if the husband, who is otherwise able to have children, loses the
opportunity to use the pre-embryos at issue, whereas the wife’s “fundamental right not to
procreate is irrevocably extinguished if a surrogate mother bears [the divorcing couple’s]
child”).
73
See Reber, 42 A.3d at 1135 n.5 (criticizing the contemporaneous approach as “totally
unrealistic. If the parties could reach an agreement, they would not be in court”).
74
See Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 31 (observing that the
contemporaneous mutual consent model “‘give[s] each progenitor a powerful bargaining chip
at a time when individuals might very well be tempted to punish their soon-to-be ex-spouses,’
‘[which] makes no sense and may invite individuals to hold hostage their ex-partner’s ability to
parent a biologically related child in order to punish or to gain other advantages’” (citing Mark
P. Strasser, You Take the Embryos but I Get the House (and the Business): Recent Trends in
Awards Involving Embryos upon Divorce, 57 B
UFF. L. REV. 1159, 1225 (2009))); see also Davis,
842 S.W.2d at 598 (“[The] problem with maintaining the status quo is that the viability of the
pre[-]embryos cannot be guaranteed indefinitely. . . . Thus, the true effect of the intermediate
court’s opinion is to confer on [the party opposing implantation] the inherent power to veto
any transfer of the pre[-]embryos in this case and thus to insure their eventual discard or self-
destruction.”); Shapo, supra note
5, at 103 (“One party’s holdout ‘right’ not to be a parent and
to dispose of pre-embryos becomes a vetoand perhaps a bargaining chip in divorceover the
other party’s ‘right’ to be a parent.”).
75
The court in Kass v. Kass noted that the contemporaneous approach effectively
undermines “the seriousness and integrity of the consent process.” 91 N.Y.2d 554, 566 (1998).
The court in that case aptly observed that “[a]dvance agreements as to disposition would have
little purpose if they were enforceable only in the event the parties continued to agree.” Id.
76
“Pacta sunt servanda” is an expression signifying that agreements in a contract must be
observed. See Pacta sunt servanda, F
REE DICTIONARY, http://legal-
dictionary.thefreedictionary.com/Pacta+Sunt+Servanda (last visited Jan. 4, 2016). As applied,
the doctrine would be the basis for enforcing the original pre-disposition contract where the
party freely agreed to the possibility of a child by donating his sperm or her eggs.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1892 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
the contemporaneous approach, like the constitutional balancing test, is
riddled with both theoretical and practical problems, warranting the
conclusion that a predisposition contract is the preferred method for
determining disputes about frozen pre-embryos in a divorce
proceeding.
Notwithstanding that the predisposition approach may be the best
relative choice amongst the three existing legal frameworks, such
contracts are open to criticism both in terms of procedural and
substantive fairness.
77
The procedural fairness concerns arise because
pre-directives as to unused frozen pre-embryos are contained in long
informed consent forms containing many provisions extraneous to
disposition upon divorce.
78
Moreover, informed consent forms have
limited options regarding disposition.
79
These limitations, coupled with
the array of information on the form that is off point to the issue of
disposition upon divorce, cast doubt on whether the parties’ true
intentions, as to unused frozen pre-embryos, are actually reflected.
80
The concerns about procedural fairness that arise when
dispositional language is contained in an informed consent form are
heightened because such forms are, in essence, a contract between the
spouses as a unit and the medical facility, as opposed to an agreement
between the two progenitors.
81
As the court in J.B. v. M.B.
82
recognized,
77
See Waldman, infra note 120. The concerns about substantive fairness, discussed in
further detail below, center on intervening events that make present enforcement of a
predisposition contract fundamentally unfair.
78
See, e.g., Cahill v. Cahill, 757 So. 2d 465, 466 (Ala. Civ. App. 2000) (noting that the
consent form was seven pages long); Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 558 (noting that the language directing
the parties to make dispositional decisions was included in several places within the twelve
page, single-spaced form); Szafranski, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, 4 (“Besides outlining the
risks involved with in vitro fertilization, the informed consent states that ‘[n]o use can be made
of these embryos without the consent of both partners.’”); see also J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707,
719 (N.J. 2001) (“Principles of fairness dictate that agreements provided by a clinic should be
written in plain language, and that a qualified clinic representative should review the terms with
the parties prior to execution.”).
79
See Cahill, 757 So. 2d at 466 (noting as the pertinent language on disposition a list limited
to five set options).
80
Cahill is illustrative as a case where doubt exists about whether the parties’ actual intent
is reflected on a consent form. Because the parties did not introduce into evidence the executed
informed consent, the court had nothing but language set forth on a blank form with which to
determine the wife’s application for an award of the pre-embryos. The court was constrained in
its decision and could only conclude that the parties “appear[]” to have determined that the
medical facility would keep the pre-embryos in the event of divorce. Id. at 467.
81
See J.B., 783 A.2d at 15 (discussing how the lower court granted summary judgment
awarding frozen pre-embryos to the wife after “noting that there was no written contract
memorializing the parties’ intentions” despite the existence of a consent form); see also Fuselier,
supra note 11, at 172 (noting that informed consent forms “represent agreements with the
clinics with respect to actions the clinics should or should not take regarding the pre-embryos
stored there. The contracts are not agreements between the parties themselves”).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1893
this distinction is important because consent forms may not accurately
reflect the spouses’ genuine intentions regarding the disposition of
frozen pre-embryos. Indeed, the lower court virtually ignored the
consent form in J.B., instead discerning intent from the parties’
certifications that accompanied their respective motions for summary
judgment in the divorce proceeding.
83
Likewise, the New Jersey
Supreme Court held in this case that the contract the parties entered
into as a unit with the medical facility did not disclose their
unambiguous intentions as to the disposition of the pre-embryos.
84
By
honing in on the absence of a discrete contract between the spouses, the
court in J.B. gave credence to the procedural fairness problems that arise
when applying the predisposition approach in a divorce action.
Other courts, however, have focused on the substantive fairness
problems associated with this approach. For example, in Davis, the
court recognized that the intense emotions associated with efforts to
overcome infertility impede true informed consent.
85
Likewise, the court
in Witten observed that the disposition of frozen pre-embryos is a
matter of such fundamental personal importance that individuals must
be allowed to opt out of their pre-directive contracts at the time of
enforcement.
86
The Szafranski court concurred that the predisposition
approach largely ignores the fact that intervening events could alter
one’s views of parenthood.
87
In each of these cases, the court voiced
82
J.B., 783 A.2d at 71112, 719; see also A.Z. v. B.Z., 725 N.E.2d 1051, 1056 (Mass. 2000)
(noting the informed consent “does not state, and the record does not indicate, that the
husband and wife intended the consent form to act as a binding agreement between them
should they later disagree as to the disposition” of the pre-embryos).
83
More specifically, the wife maintained that, at the time of IVF, she and her husband
“agreed to preserve the pre[-]embryos for our use in the context of an intact family.” J.B., 783
A.2d at 710. Thus, she wanted the remaining embryos destroyed. By contrast, the husband
swore that he and his wife “had agreed that no matter what happened the eggs would be either
utilized by us or by other infertile couples.Id. Thus, he sought an order permitting the
remaining pre-embryos to be donated following his divorce. Id.
84
Id. at 713 (noting the language in the agreement conditioning the relinquishment of the
frozen pre-embryos to the medical facility unless the court ordered otherwise).
85
The Davis court acknowledged that informed consent is necessarily impeded as
“anticipating . . . all the turns that events may take as the IVF process unfolds” becomes
impossible. Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 597 (Tenn. 1992). Yet despite this recognition, the
Davis court would permit a modification of the initial contract only if one of the progenitors
has no other reasonable way of becoming a parent, thereby diluting somewhat its concerns
about substantive fairness when applying the predisposition approach. See id. at 604.
86
See In re Marriage of Witten, 672 N.W.2d 768, 777 (Iowa 2003). As such, the court found
that “individuals are entitled to make decisions consistent with their contemporaneous wishes,
values, and beliefs.” Id.
87
See Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, ¶ 19 (stating that the predisposition
approach “ignores the difficulty of predicting one’s future response to life-altering events such
as parenthood” (quoting Witten, 672 N.W.2d at 777)); accord Waldman, infra note 120, at 935
(“Time, relatively unimportant to men, but of crucial importance to women, may work rather
dramatic changes in a woman’s interest in using a particular embryo for reproduction.”).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1894 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
concern that the terms of a predisposition contract may no longer be
substantively fair at the time of divorce such that some form of
safeguard is warranted.
88
This Note posits that courts may resolve this
concern and assure that predisposition contracts are both procedurally
and substantively fair by adhering to the paradigm of prenuptial and
surrogacy agreements.
III.
THE PREDISPOSITION APPROACH SHOULD BE HONED WITH
REFERENCE TO THE PARADIGM OF PRENUPTIAL AND SURROGACY
AGREEMENTS
The paradigm of prenuptial and surrogacy agreements is well-
suited to addressing, if not resolving, the criticisms regarding
procedural and substantive fairness directed at the predisposition
contract in the event of divorce. Under this paradigm, both
voluntariness and intervening events are factors in deciding whether or
not to enforce the prenuptial or surrogacy agreement at issue,
considerations which also may apply to assure that predisposition
contracts are fair.
89
Prenuptial agreements are also similar to
predisposition agreements in terms of history, concept, and genre.
90
Such similarities give further credence to the proposition that prenuptial
agreements are a solid and workable model for contracts disposing of
pre-embryos. Likewise, surrogacy agreements are akin to predisposition
agreements in that both pertain to the use of a pre-embryo, albeit in
different factual contexts. The safeguards assuring that surrogacy
contracts are procedurally and substantively fair are, thus, instructive in
the realm of predisposition agreements as well.
88
See Waldman, infra note 120, at 935 (“Judicial and legislative concern is warranted
because the determination to relinquish reproductive opportunities may be affected and shaken
by life events apart from pregnancy and birth.”).
89
See infra Parts IIIIV.
90
See infra Parts IIIIV.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1895
A. Both Prenuptial and Surrogacy Agreements Are Analogous to
the Predisposition Contract
1. The Prenuptial and Predisposition Agreements Are
Historically, Conceptually, and Generically Similar
a. Similarities in History Reveal that Predisposition and
Prenuptial Agreements Further the Same Public Policies, such that the
Latter May Be a Logical Paradigm for Implementing the Former
Predisposition contracts are, in the first instance, akin to prenuptial
agreements in that they share a history of reluctant acceptance. Even
though modern prenuptial agreements first appeared in the sixteenth
century and were important enough to be included in the original
Statute of Frauds,
91
they were void as against public policy in the United
States prior to 1970.
92
One of the reasons for this long-standing judicial
aversion toward prenuptial agreements was that they were thought to
promote divorce.
93
Another reason for voiding prenuptial agreements
ab initio
94
was that they were thought to commercialize marriage and to
emphasize the individual over the couple.
95
However, as more married women went to work, the judicial trend
changed toward the realization that prenuptial agreements actually
promote marital stability by permitting both spouses to lay out their
expectations and to protect their individually-held assets.
96
91
Judith T. Younger, Perspectives on Antenuptial Agreements: An Update, 8 J. AM. ACAD.
MATRIM. LAW. 1, 2 (1992).
92
In Posner v. Posner, 257 So. 2d 530 (Fla. 1972), the Florida Supreme Court upheld a
prenuptial agreement containing spousal support provisions which had previously been
deemed void as against public policy, thereby initiating the trend toward enforcing such
contracts.
93
Indeed, escalator clauses under which the amount of property increases upon attaining
certain marriage milestones still may be void ab initio as promoting divorce. See Jonathan E.
Fields, Forbidden Provisions in Prenuptial Agreements: Legal and Practical Considerations for
the Matrimonial Lawyer, 21 J. A
M. ACAD. MATRIM. LAW. 413, 415 (2008) (citing Davis v. Davis,
No. FA 950144807S, 1996 WL 456335 (Conn. Super. Ct., July 29, 1996)).
94
“Ab initio” is defined as “from the inception.” Ab Initio, FREE DICTIONARY, http://legal-
dictionary.thefreedictionary.com/ab+initio (last visited Jan. 12, 2016).
95
See Allison A. Marston, Note, Planning for Love: The Politics of Prenuptial Agreements,
49 S
TAN. L. REV. 887, 89394 (1997).
96
See, e.g., In re Marriage of Pendleton, 72 Cal. Rptr. 2d 840, 848 (Ct. App. 1998)
(“[P]remarital agreements may in fact encourage rather than discourage marriage. As more
than one court has noted, society’s current acceptance of cohabitation without marriage offers
an attractive alternative to a wealthy man or woman who cannot marry without relinquishing
the right to limit his or her spousal support obligation in the event of divorce.”); Newman v.
Newman, 653 P.2d 728, 732 (Colo. 1982) (“[I]t is reasonable to believe that such planning
brings a greater stability to the marriage relation by protecting the financial expectations of the
parties, and does not necessarily encourage or contribute to dissolution.”).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1896 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
Commentators have also observed that prenuptial agreements are on
the rise because the prevalence of divorce and remarriage encourages
couples to plan carefully, independently, and realistically for their
economic future.
97
The same observation about careful and realistic planning applies
in response to those opposed to enforcing predisposition contracts at
the time of divorce. As with prenuptial agreements, such resistance is
based on public policy, particularly on the notion that prior directives
for disposing of pre-embryos are void ab initio as compelling one
spouse to become a parent against his or her will.
98
Yet, as with
prenuptial agreements, the public policy that concerns the critics is, in
fact, promoted through judicial recognition and regulation of the
objectionable contracts, rather than leaving them hostage to the extra-
legal regime of the relationship.
99
Indeed, instead of stifling
procreational freedom, predisposition agreements actually promote this
liberty by allowing the spouses to discuss the options as to unused pre-
embryos and, together, arrive at a cogent expression of their
intentions.
100
This common historical background is the first of several
similarities that make prenuptial agreements a logical paradigm for
addressing concerns about predisposition contracts.
b. Prenuptial and Predisposition Agreements Are Fundamentally
Similar in Concept, Suggesting that the Former Could Be a Paradigm for
the Latter
Prenuptial and predisposition agreements are also conceptually
similar, in that both seek to diminish the state’s involvement in the
marital relationship, notwithstanding that as long ago as 1888, the U.S.
Supreme Court declared marriage to be “a great public institution,
giving character to our whole civil polity.
101
This characterization as a
“public institution” is the historic basis for state involvement in the
marital relationship.
102
Thus, when a couple marries, they are
97
Marston, supra note 95, at 891.
98
See, e.g., A.Z. v. B.Z., 725 N.E.2d 1051, 1058 (Mass. 2000) (stating that “forced
procreation is not an area amenable to judicial enforcement” such that prior directive contracts
violate public policy); J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 71819 (N.J. 2001) (“[A]greements [that]
compel procreation over the subsequent objection of one of the parties . . . are violative of
public policy.”).
99
See Litowitz v. Litowitz, 48 P.3d 261, 267 (Wash. 2002) (recognizing that predisposition
contracts “maximize procreative liberty by reserving to the progenitors the authority to make
what is in the first instance a quintessentially personal, private decision.” (quoting Kass v. Kass,
91 N.Y.2d 554, 565 (1998))).
100
Id.
101
See Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 213 (1888) (quoting Noel v. Ewing, 9 Ind. 37, 50
(1857)).
102
Marston, supra note 95, at 902.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1897
subscribing to an entire set of legal rights and responsibilities as
determined by the state-created “marriage contract.
103
Terms
pertaining to property distribution in the event of divorce are included
in this contract.
104
The idea of a prenuptial agreement is for the parties to amend the
default provisions of this marriage contract upon dissolution so as to
dictate for themselves the terms of their spousal relationship, should it
come to an end by divorce.
105
The rapid social changes that have
occurred in American family life in recent times, including the
prevalence of divorce and remarriage, justify the opportunity for
spouses to dictate the terms of property distribution upon marital
dissolution.
106
Likewise, the increased usage of IVF supports permitting couples
to dictate the terms by which unused frozen pre-embryos will be
disposed should the marriage end in divorce.
107
As the New Jersey
Supreme Court aptly observed, the law has not kept pace with advances
in medical technology, which have enabled new reproductive
opportunities.
108
The need for such legal principles, however, would be
obviated by virtue of the predisposition contract that, like the prenuptial
agreement, is a means by which the states’ role in a couple’s marriage
may be diminished.
c. Generic Similarities Further Support the Proposition that
Prenuptial Contracts May Be Models for Predisposition Agreements
Prenuptial agreements and predisposition contracts regarding
unused frozen pre-embryos are also generically similar. First, they both
deal with the disposition of property upon divorce. The Uniform
Premarital Agreement Act (UPAA),
109
drafted in 1983 to provide
national consistency to the terms of prenuptial agreements, lists eight
permissible subjects for inclusion in these contracts, six of which deal
with property rights.
110
103
Id. at 901.
104
Id. at 902.
105
Id. at 903 (observing that the states’ willingness to permit such variations “parallels a
trend throughout family law in which private norm creation and decisionmaking have trumped
state-imposed rules”).
106
Id.
107
See supra note 2.
108
See J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 715 (N.J. 2001) (“Advances in medical technology have far
outstripped the development of legal principles to resolve the inevitable disputes arising out of
the new reproductive opportunities now available.”).
109
See UNIF. PREMARITAL AGREEMENT ACT §§ 3(a)(1)(6) (UNIF. LAW COMMN 1983).
110
The eight permissible subjects are:
(1) [T]he rights and obligations of each of the parties in any of the property of either
or both of them whenever and wherever acquired or located; (2) the right to buy, sell,
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1898 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
Similarly, frozen pre-embryos are considered property, albeit
property entitled to “special respect,”
111
a status that the Tennessee
Supreme Court in Davis deemed proper in 1992 when considering
whether pre-embryos should be “persons” for purposes of determining
their disposition. In concluding that pre-embryos are not persons, the
court was guided by the reasoning set forth in Roe v. Wade,
112
whereby
the U.S. Supreme Court held that a fetus has no independent legal
rights.
113
Ultimately, the Davis court concluded that pre-embryos
occupy an interim category in which they are less than a person but
more than mere chattel because of their potential to become human
life.
114
Thus, as with other property to be distributed in accordance with
the terms of a prenuptial agreement, spouses have an ownership interest
in the disposition of pre-embryos, which may be addressed in a contract
between them.
115
Likewise, both prenuptial and predisposition contracts share
temporal similarities, in that both are to be performed, if ever, in the
future.
116
The possibility thus exists in both instances that intervening
use, transfer, exchange, abandon, lease, consume, expend, assign, create a security
interest in, mortgage, encumber, dispose of, or otherwise manage and control
property; (3) the disposition of property upon separation, marital dissolution, death,
or the occurrence or nonoccurrence of any other event; (4) the modification or
elimination of spousal support; (5) the making of a will, trust, or other arrangement
to carry out the provisions of the agreement; (6) the ownership rights in and
disposition of the death benefit from a life insurance policy; (7) the choice of law
governing the construction of the agreement; and (8) any other matter, including
their personal rights and obligations, not in violation of public policy or a statute
imposing a criminal penalty.
Id.
111
See Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 597 (Tenn. 1992). But cf. Kass v. Kass, 91 N.Y.2d 554,
56465 (1998) (agreeing that pre-zygotes are not persons, but noting that “for purposes of
resolving the present appeal we have no cause to decide whether the pre-zygotes are entitled to
‘special respect’”).
112
See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973); see also Fuselier, supra note 11, at 167 (“There is a
human life component to the pre-embryosthe potential for human life to developmaking
them inherently special. They deserve their own classification.”).
113
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 595 (citing Roe v. Wade and noting that the Supreme Court
“explicitly refused to hold that the fetus possesses independent rights under law, based upon a
thorough examination of the federal constitution, relevant common law principles, and the lack
of scientific consensus as to when life begins” (footnote omitted)).
114
Id. at 597 (“[P]re[-]embryos are not, strictly speaking, either ‘persons’ or ‘property,’ but
occupy an interim category that entitles them to special respect because of their potential for
human life.”).
115
Id. (“[Spouses] do have an interest in the nature of ownership, to the extent that they
have decision-making authority concerning disposition of the pre[-]embryos, within the scope
of policy set by law.”); see also Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131, 1133 (Pa. Super. Ct. 2012) (“The
parties agree, as does the [trial] court, that the pre-embryos are marital property subject to
equitable distribution.”).
116
See Kass, 91 N.Y.2d at 565 (stating that “[a]ll agreements looking to the future to some
extent deal with the unknown,” but adding that “the uncertainties inherent in the IVF process
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1899
events not foreseeable at the time of execution will make enforcement
unfair.
117
The passage of time between execution and enforcement in
both instances gives rise to the need for a heightened standard of review
that assures procedural and substantive fairness to protect against
unconscionable results.
Finally, the two types of contracts have in common the parties
two spouses who are in a confidential relationship.
118
As such, in each
instance, the parties do not deal at arm’s length, but rather must bargain
with candor, good faith, and sincerity in connection with all matters
regarding the agreement.
119
This duty of candor is particularly
important to the woman, who in each instance is often the
disadvantaged party.
120
Thus, the safeguards that courts impose to
protect against unconscionability when enforcing a prenuptial
agreement should also be considered for their effectiveness in the
context of a predisposition contract pertaining to frozen pre-embryos at
the time of divorce.
2. Predisposition Contracts Can Gain Force from Surrogacy
Agreements, Another Type of Ante-Natal Contract Whose Enforcement
Is Predicated upon Procedural and Substantive Fairness
Surrogacy contracts, like predisposition agreements, deal with the
use of reproductive assistance, though the former pertains to a gestator
itself are vastly complicated by cryopreservation, which extends the viability of pre-zygotes
indefinitely and allows time for minds, and circumstances, to change”).
117
See infra Section III.B.
118
See, e.g., Braddock v. Braddock, 542 P.2d 1060, 1062 (Nev. 1975) (applying Ohio law, the
court stated “[a]n engagement to marry creates a confidential relation between the contracting
parties and an antenuptial contract entered into after the engagement and during its pendency
must be attended by the utmost good faith” (quoting Juhasz v. Juhasz, 16 N.E.2d 328, 331 (Ohio
1938))).
119
Id.
120
See Marston, supra note 95, at 911 (“Because women are often financially or emotionally
disadvantaged in the bargaining process, they contest prenuptials at much greater rates than
men. . . . Regardless of age, empirical data indicate that women generally fare worse than men
in economic negotiations.”); see also Younger, supra note 91, at 19 n.83 (citing cases where
husband had both greater assets and sophistication in business negotiation). Similarly, women
are often the disadvantaged party in a predisposition contract. See Ellen A. Waldman, Disputing
over Embryos: Of Contracts and Consents, 32 A
RIZ. ST. L.J. 897, 928 (2000) (“[D]ispositional
agreements that preclude the unilateral use of embryos in the event of divorce are substantively
skewed against the woman.”). Because men are capable of producing sperm well into their
seventies and women’s ability to produce viable eggs diminishes after age thirty-five, IVF often
occurs in the latter’s reproductive prime with divorce happening in the twilight of her fertile
years. Thus, as with a prenuptial agreement, safeguards must be in place to assure that the
husband has not overreached where the predisposition contract precludes a unilateral award of
the pre-embryos to the wife.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1900 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
becoming pregnant with another’s pre-embryo in exchange for a fee.
121
In particular, the gestator agrees in advance of the pregnancy to
relinquish all parental rights to the intended parents.
122
These
agreements take two distinct forms.
123
The first is a Pre-Planned Adoption Agreement, also known as a
Traditional Surrogacy Agreement.
124
This arrangement typically
involves a surrogate donating her ovum and being artificially
inseminated with the sperm from the husband of a couple whose wife is
infertile.
125
Following delivery and the surrogate’s relinquishment of
parental rights, the wife adopts the baby and becomes the legal parent.
The second type, known as a Gestational Surrogacy Agreement, involves
a surrogate who has no biological ties to the resulting baby.
126
Through
IVF, a pre-embryo is created from either the intended father’s sperm
with a donor egg, the intended mother’s egg with donor sperm, or the
egg and sperm from the intended parents.
127
As with predisposition
contracts,
128
both types of surrogacy agreements have impassioned
opponents as well as supporters.
129
121
Roman v. Roman, 193 S.W.3d 40, 49 (Tex. App. 2006) (defining a gestational agreement
as “an agreement between a woman and the intended parents of a child in which the woman
relinquishes all rights as a parent of a child conceived by means of assisted reproduction and
which provides that the intended parents become the parents of the child”); In re Baby, 447
S.W.3d 807, 818 (Tenn. 2014) (defining surrogacy as “[t]he process of carrying and delivering a
child for another person” (quoting Surrogacy, B
LACKS LAW DICTIONARY (9th ed. 2009)));
Johnson v. Calvert, 851 P.2d 776, 77778 (Cal. 1993), modified on other grounds by In re C.K.G.,
173 S.W.3d 714 (Tenn. 2005).
122
Roman, 193 S.W.3d at 49.
123
In re Baby, 447 S.W.3d at 818.
124
See id. at 812 (defining the traditional surrogacy contract as one “which involves the
artificial insemination of the surrogate, who, after giving birth, is meant to relinquish the child
to the biological father and the intended mother”).
125
Martha A. Field, Compensated Surrogacy, 89 WASH. L. REV. 1155, 1156 (2014).
126
See In re Marriage of Moschetta, 25 Cal. App. 4th 1218, 1222 (Dist. Ct. App. 1994)
(defining a gestational surrogacy contract as one “where the sperm of the married man is
artificially united with the egg of his wife, and the resulting embryo [is placed] in another
woman’s womb”); see also Browne C. Lewis, Due Date: Enforcing Surrogacy Promises in the Best
Interest of the Child, 87 S
T. JOHNS L. REV. 899, 900 (2013).
127
See Moschetta, 25 Cal. App. 4th at 1222; see also Lewis, supra note 126, at 90203.
128
See supra Section III.C.
129
The process [of surrogacy] has evoked much discussion: medical, biological,
sociological, philosophical, psychological, religious, economic, logical, emotional,
and legal. It has been variously characterized by its proponents as, inter alia . . . a “gift
of life” to childless couples, one that . . . implement[s] the principal’s right to obtain a
baby, and one that is sensitive to the needs of infertile couples. . . . The opponents
have characterized surrogacy as, inter alia: the illegal and unconstitutional purchase
and sale of human beings, babies for profit, “rent a womb” . . . and a threat to human
dignity.
James T. Flaherty, Enforcement of Surrogate Mother Contracts: Case Law, the Uniform Acts, and
State and Federal Legislation, 36 C
LEV. ST. L. REV. 223, 22425 (1988).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1901
Those opposed to these sorts of ante-natal contracts maintain that
they relegate children to a commodity and, further, that they exploit and
devalue impoverished women.
130
Such critics believe, therefore, the
surrogacy agreements of either type should be void as against public
policy.
131
The New Jersey Supreme Court agreed with those opponents
in its landmark In re Baby M
132
decision invalidating a surrogacy
contract as violating public policy.
133
In other states, the legislatures
have prohibited surrogacy contracts.
134
By contrast, those in favor of surrogacy agreements counter that a
woman should have the freedom to contract for the use of her own
body, including in instances where doing so is for economic gain.
135
Furthermore, supporters arguing from the perspective of the intended
parents maintain that banning surrogacy contracts is akin to interfering
with the right to procreate.
136
Thus, they maintain that surrogacy
arrangements enjoy constitutional protection.
137
In light of this fervent and ongoing debate, surrogacy contracts are
scrutinized for procedural and substantive safeguards in the states
where they are permitted.
138
Such scrutiny is instructive in the realm of
predisposition contracts as demonstrating that ante-natal agreements
are an effective model, provided they are fair.
B. Safeguards to Assure Procedural Fairness in the Realm of
Prenuptial and Surrogacy Agreements Would Also Address the Concerns
About Predisposition Contracts Pertaining to Frozen Pre-Embryos
To protect against the risk of overreaching and unconscionable
results, prenuptial and surrogacy agreements must be both procedurally
130
Lewis, supra note 126, at 923, 940. In actuality, this concern may be misguided as “based
upon the erroneous perception that surrogates are poor, uneducated women who are preyed
upon by wealthy, infertile couples. Research indicates that the average surrogate is a middle-
income, educated woman who has had other children.” Id. at 923.
131
See supra note 129.
132
In re Baby M, 537 A.2d 1227 (N.J. 1988).
133
Id. at 411 (“We find the payment of money to a ‘surrogate’ mother illegal, perhaps
criminal, and potentially degrading to women.”); see also Richard F. Storrow, New Thinking on
Commercial Surrogacy, 88 I
ND. L.J. 1281, 1281 (2013) (“[J]urisdictions that prohibit surrogacy
view it as per se exploitative and as inappropriately commodifying human reproduction . . . .”).
134
See, e.g., MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. §§ 722.851.863 (West 2011) (voiding surrogacy
contracts and imposing criminal penalties).
135
Field, supra note 125, at 1172 (asking the rhetorical question: “When an intelligent
woman consents to such a relationship, why should she be unable to bind herself by her
promise because others feel that the arrangement exploits her?”).
136
Id. at 1178.
137
Id. at 117778.
138
See infra Sections III.B.2, III.C.2.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1902 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
and substantively fair.
139
Legislatures and courts have often blurred
these two aspects of fairness as they are closely related.
140
Nonetheless,
both aspects of fairness serve to assure that prenuptial and surrogacy
agreements are properly enforceable. The safeguards such fairness
requirements provide in the context of these agreements would also
resolve the concerns critics have voiced about divorce courts deciding
pre-embryo disputes through the enforcement of a predisposition
contract.
141
1. Procedural Fairness in the Context of Prenuptial Agreements
Requires Voluntariness and Full Disclosure of Finances
Procedural fairness seeks to assure that the bargaining process is
free of coerciveness and other defects that suggest one party did not
make an intended choice such that the resulting agreement would be
unenforceable.
142
In Gant v. Gant,
143
the court bluntly recognized that
parties to a prenuptial agreement are often mismatched in terms of
bargaining power.
144
Thus, procedural fairness in that context requires
that the agreement be entered into voluntarily, after both sides have
fully disclosed their finances to the other.
145
A prenuptial agreement
meeting these criteria is fairly procured.
146
The relevant period of
judicial review is the time the agreement was executed.
147
The inquiry into voluntariness in this regard exceeds that
undertaken in the commercial context for fraud, overreaching, or sharp
139
Younger, supra note 91, at 7, 18.
140
Id. at 18 (“If the substantive terms of an agreement seem fair to the reviewing court,
operating with or without statutory guidance, procedural niceties become less important.
Conversely, if the agreement seems unfair, the procedures surrounding its execution become
more important.”); see also Waldman, supra note 120, at 927 (“Commentators and courts have
suggested that, in practice, the two elements of unconscionability are measured according to a
sliding scale. A grotesquely one-sided contract might be voided with only a slight showing of
procedural defectiveness. Conversely, clear defects in the bargaining process might be sufficient
to nullify a contract whose terms, though problematic, cannot be said to ‘shock the
conscience.’” (footnote omitted)).
141
See infra Part IV.
142
Waldman, supra note 120, at 926.
143
329 S.E.2d 106 (W. Va. 1985), overruled by Ware v. Ware, 687 S.E.2d 382 (W. Va. 2009).
However, the proposition that parties to a prenuptial agreement often have unequal bargaining
power remains true.
144
Id. at 114 (“[C]andor compels us to raise to a conscious level the fact that, as in this case,
prenuptial agreements will almost always be entered into between people with property or an
income potential to protect on one side and people who are impecunious on the other.”).
145
Younger, supra note 91, at 19.
146
Id. at 18.
147
Id.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1903
dealing.
148
In the context of a prenuptial agreement, voluntariness also
considers such factors as the parties’ sophistication in worldly affairs,
the timing of the execution relative to the wedding, and the opportunity
to seek independent counsel.
149
Notably, the retention of independent counsel is not a decisive
criterion for determining voluntariness and, thus, procedural fairness.
150
Rather, the key concern from both the legislative and judicial
perspective is whether the party challenging the prenuptial agreement
had an opportunity to seek legal advice.
151
The 2012 Uniform Premarital
and Marital Agreement Act (UPMAA)
152
evinces this concern in section
9, which states in relevant part that a premarital agreement is
unenforceable if a party against whom enforcement is sought did not
have access to independent legal counsel.
153
Some courts, likewise, do not require the actual advice of legal
counsel in order to find a prenuptial agreement being challenged as
procedurally unfair nonetheless enforceable. In Pajak v. Pajak,
154
the
court upheld a prenuptial agreement that the wife argued was not fairly
procured due to her not having had legal counsel.
155
Notably, the court
reasoned that independent advice from an attorney is not a requirement
for enforcing a prenuptial agreement when the terms are
comprehensible to a reasonably intelligent adult.
156
Under such
circumstances, the contract at issue was procedurally fair.
157
In addition to voluntariness, procedural fairness in the realm of a
prenuptial agreement requires that the parties candidly disclose their
finances to each other prior to execution.
158
The requirement of
financial disclosure is closely related to voluntariness and, indeed, flows
148
Id. at 1920.
149
See Norris v. Norris, 419 A.2d 982, 985 (D.C. 1980); Simeone v. Simeone, 581 A.2d 162,
167 (Pa. 1990).
150
See, e.g., UNIF. PREMARITAL & MARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 9(a)(2) (UNIF. LAW COMMN
2012).
151
Id.; see also Younger, supra note 91, at 22.
152
UNIF. PREMARITAL & MARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 9(a)(2).
153
Id.
154
Pajak v. Pajak, 385 S.E.2d 384 (W. Va. 1989).
155
Id. at 38889; see also In re Estate of Baker, 207 S.W.3d 254, 267 (Tenn. Ct. App. 2006)
(“[S]ome states hold that the presence or absence of independent counsel is just another factor
to be considered when determining if the agreement was entered into knowledgeably.”).
156
See Pajak, 385 S.E.2d at 38889 (“[A]dvice of independent counsel at the time parties
enter into a pre-nuptial agreement helps demonstrate that there has been no fraud, duress or
misrepresentation, and that the agreement was entered into knowledgeably and voluntarily,
[but] such independent advice of counsel is not a prerequisite to enforceability when the terms
of the agreement are understandable to a reasonably intelligent adult and both parties have had
the opportunity to consult with independent counsel.”); see also In re Estate of Baker, 207
S.W.3d at 26770.
157
See generally Younger, supra note 91, at 26.
158
Id. at 2427.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1904 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
from the nature of prenuptial agreements themselves.
159
These
agreements either waive or modify marital property rights, the value of
which derives from the spouses’ assets.
160
The waiver of all or any
portion of such rights cannot be voluntary, and thus cannot be fairly
procured, absent full financial disclosure prior to execution.
161
The extent of the required disclosure varies from case to case
depending on several factors. Among these is the parties’ relative
worldliness.
162
Some courts require the more sophisticated party to a
prenuptial agreement to inform the prospective spouse as to the rights
being waived.
163
Likewise, the existence of a disproportional provision
164
is another factor that some courts consider when determining fair
procurement, leading to a presumption that disclosure may have been
insufficient in such instance.
165
The variety and degree of factors that
courts contemplate prompts the conclusion that procedural fairness in
the context of a prenuptial agreement requires enough disclosure so that
each contracting party has a clear idea of the other’s property and
resources. Those parties that do will have entered into a fairly procured
prenuptial agreement that is both voluntary and grounded upon candid
communication underlying the parties’ true intentions.
2. Surrogacy Contracts Are Procedurally Fair if the Parties Have
Had the Opportunity to Seek Independent Counsel, Compensation Is
Reasonable, and the Gestator Has the Right to Rescind Following
Delivery
A key criterion for determining whether a surrogacy contract is
procedurally fair corresponds to one of the main safeguards considered
159
Id.
160
Id.
161
Id.
162
See, e.g., Kosik v. George, 452 P.2d 560, 56364 (Or. 1969) (requiring husband with
business savvy to fully inform wife of the rights she was forfeiting under the prenuptial
agreement); cf. Hengel v. Hengel, 365 N.W.2d 16, 20 (Wis. Ct. App. 1985) (finding that wife
who had moderate sophistication in financial matters need only be provided with information
to enable “a general and approximate knowledge” of husband’s property).
163
Kosik, 452 P.2d at 56364.
164
A disproportional provision is a contractual term that favors one party over the other.
165
See, e.g., Schmidt v. Schmidt, 9 Va. Cir. 273, 278 (Cir. Ct. 1987) (discussing Batleman v.
Rubin, 98 S.E.2d 519 (Va. 1957)) (raising presumption that husband did not provide full and
frank disclosure prior to executing prenuptial agreement where wife agreed to accept a sum less
than a third of the value of his property); Friedlander v. Friedlander, 494 P.2d 208, 213 (Wash.
1972) (en banc) (Where a pre-nuptial contract makes provision for a wife that is
disproportionate to the means of the intended husband, it casts a burden upon the intended
husband, and those claiming under him, to prove that she had full knowledge of all the facts
and circumstances that materially affected the contract.”).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1905
in the realm of prenuptial agreements: voluntariness.
166
As in the
domain of prenuptial agreements, procedural fairness in the realm of
surrogacy arrangements includes the opportunity to seek legal advice.
167
Other aspects of the procedural fairness inquiry aim to assure that the
surrogate is not coerced into the ante-natal agreement. Such safeguards
are akin to those intended to protect the disadvantaged party
168
in a
prenuptial agreement, which protections this Note argues pertain to
predisposition contracts as well.
169
Two such safeguards in favor of the surrogate relate to
compensation and to the opportunity to rescind the agreement
relinquishing parental rights.
170
To assure that the surrogacy contract is
truly voluntary and not the result of intended parents exploiting a
gestator in financial need, some states prohibit the former from paying
anything to the latter,
171
whereas in other states the amount of
compensation is limited.
172
Other than payment for reasonable expenses
attendant with the pregnancy, no bonus or supplement of any kind is
permitted.
173
Where compensation is permitted, it may not be
contingent upon actually surrendering the child, as the surrogate must
have the option to rescind her promise to terminate parental rights.
174
Indeed, the opportunity to exercise that termination right post-
delivery is another procedural safeguard that some courts apply to
assure voluntariness.
175
In A.H.W. v. G.H.B.,
176
plaintiffs were intended
166
See supra Section III.B.1; see also Roman v. Roman, 193 S.W.3d 40, 49 (Tex. App. 2006)
(“To validate a gestational agreement, the court must find . . . that each party to the agreement
voluntarily entered into and understood the terms of the agreement.”).
167
See, e.g., FLA. STAT. ANN. § 63.213(4) (West 2012) (requiring the parties to a surrogacy
contract to have independent counsel); Adoption of Matthew B., 284 Cal. Rptr. 18, 28 (Ct. App.
1991) (enforcing agreement where the surrogate had independent legal counsel to protect her
interests and to assure that the arrangement was knowing and voluntary).
168
See supra note 120.
169
See infra Part IV.
170
See infra notes 171174.
171
See, e.g., WASH. REV. CODE ANN. § 26.26.240 (West 2016) (providing that surrogate
parentage contracts, whether executed in Washington or elsewhere, that provide for
compensation are void as against public policy and unenforceable in the State of Washington).
172
See, e.g., FLA. STAT. ANN. § 63.213(f) (limiting payment to reasonable legal and medical
fees, living expenses, lost wages, and compensation for the medical risk); In re Baby, 447 S.W.3d
807, 82627 (Tenn. 2014) (noting that compensation provisions will be enforced only to the
extent they pertain to expenses inherent in the surrogacy process itself).
173
See, e.g., FLA. STAT. ANN. § 63.213(f) (“[N]o other compensation, whether in cash or in
kind, shall be made pursuant to a preplanned adoption arrangement.”).
174
See, e.g., In re Baby, 447 S.W.3d at 826 (“[C]ompensation to a traditional surrogate
should not be contingent upon her surrender of the child or the termination of her parental
rights.”).
175
See, e.g., FLA. STAT. ANN. § 63.213(1)(b) (providing surrogate mother with forty-eight
hours after delivery to revoke consent to adoption if the child is genetically related to her); see
also In re Marriage of Moschetta, 25 Cal. App. 4th 1218, 1235 (Ct. App. 1994) (“[T]here
is . . . no doubt that enforcement of a surrogacy contract prior to a child’s birth presents a host
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1906 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
parents who entered into a gestational surrogacy contract pursuant to
which defendant family member agreed to be implanted with their
embryo.
177
Prior to defendant’s due date, plaintiffs commenced a
proceeding for an order declaring themselves the unborn child’s legal
mother and father.
178
Though the surrogate did not oppose plaintiffs’
requested relief,
179
the court nonetheless denied the petition,
emphasizing the right to rescind as a key aspect of procedural
fairness.
180
Specifically, the court emphasized the emotional and biological
changes that occur during pregnancy,
181
as well as the bond that is
created between a surrogate and the baby she carries.
182
In recognition
of this bond, the court would not allow the surrogacy contract to be
used as a mechanism through which to coerce a gestator
183
into
relinquishing her parental rights
184
via a pre-delivery order that directs
the intended parents to be listed on the birth certificate. The court
instead required the parties to abide by a seventy-two hour waiting
period following delivery, thereby enforcing the surrogacy contract in a
manner that respected the parties’ intentions, albeit with procedural
safeguards.
185
Accordingly, some sound precedent exists to illustrate
of thorny legal problems, particularly if such contracts were specifically enforced.”); In re Baby,
447 S.W.3d at 834 (vacating consent order issued pre-delivery based on the State’s “statutory
procedures [that] unequivocally prohibit the voluntary relinquishment of a biological birth
mother’s parental rights prior to birth through either surrender or parental consent to
adoption”).
176
A.H.W. v. G.H.B., 772 A.2d 948 (N.J. Super. Ct. Ch. Div. 2000).
177
Id. at 94950.
178
Id.
179
Id. at 949.
180
Id. at 954.
181
Id.
182
Specifically, the court stated:
A bond is created between a gestational mother and the baby she carries in her womb
for nine months. During the pregnancy, the fetus relies on the gestational mother for
a myriad of contributions. A gestational mother’s endocrine system determines the
timing, amount and components of hormones that affect the fetus. The absence of
any component at its appropriate time will irreversibly alter the life, mental capacity,
appearance, susceptibility to disease and structure of the fetus forever.
Id. at 953.
183
See id. at 954 (“A court order for the pre-birth termination of the pregnant defendant’s
parental rights is the equivalent of making her subject to a binding agreement to surrender the
child . . . .”).
184
See id. (“It is not necessary now to determine what parental rights, if any, the gestational
mother may have vis-á-vis the newborn infant. That decision will have to be made if and when
a gestational mother attempts to keep the infant after birth in violation of the prior
agreement.”).
185
See id. (acknowledging that the “parties’ detailed fifteen page agreement clearly reflects
their shared intent and desired outcome for this case” and allowing them “to the maximum
extent possible, the relief requested”). Thus, the court directed the attending physician who
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1907
how one form of ante-natal contract, that is, the surrogacy agreement,
can be utilized and enforced so that matters of reproductive choice
remain with the affected parties.
C. Substantive Fairness Protections as Applied to Prenuptial and
Surrogacy Agreements Could, Likewise, Pertain to Predisposition
Contracts
Such precedent is not limited to procedural fairness, but exists in
the realm of substantive concerns as well. Substantive unconscionability
considers whether the actual terms of a contract unreasonably favor one
of the parties so as to be shockingly unfair.
186
1. Substantive Fairness in the Realm of Prenuptial Agreements
Focuses on Unforeseen Developments that Would Cause Hardship
Courts are divided as to the temporal framework for measuring
substantive fairness in the context of prenuptial agreements, with some
looking at the time of execution, some at the time of enforcement, and
some at both.
187
The primary benefit to measuring the substantive
fairness of a prenuptial agreement at the time of execution is that the
parties’ freedom to contract receives maximum respect.
188
Yet, limiting
review to the time of execution forecloses consideration of unforeseen
intervening events that render previously reasonable provisions
substantively unfair and inequitable at the time of enforcement.
189
Thus,
courts review prenuptial agreements for substantive fairness at the time
of enforcement not to rewrite the parties’ bargain, but to avoid the
hardship and significant financial problems that would otherwise ensue
due to unforeseen developments in the marriage since execution.
190
delivered the baby to wait seventy-two hours before preparing the Certificate of Parentage,
noting “[t]his solution represents a modification of the agreement between the parties to the
least extent necessary.” Id.
186
Waldman, supra note 120, at 927 n.174 (“A substantively unconscionable contract is one
that no sensible man would make and such as no honest and fair man would accept.” (quoting
Martin Rispens & Son v. Hall Farms, Inc., 621 N.E.2d 1078, 1087 (Ind. 1993), abrogated by
Hyundai Motor Am., Inc. v. Goodin, 822 N.E.2d 947 (Ind. 2005))).
187
Younger, supra note 91, at 29.
188
See, e.g., McKee-Johnson v. Johnson, 444 N.W.2d 259, 266 (Minn. 1989), overruled by In
re Estate of Kinney, 733 N.W.2d 118 (Minn. 2007) (“Many jurisdictions, perhaps a majority,
have opted for a time of execution review, prompted, undoubtedly, by concerns relative to
freedom of contract between consenting adults.”).
189
Younger, supra note 91, at 78.
190
Id. at 18.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1908 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
The judicial emphasis is on unforeseen developments that cause
the hardship rather than on the hardship itself. For example, in Pajak,
both spouses had children from previous marriages, and the husband
had independent wealth.
191
The day before their wedding, plaintiff-
husband asked that defendant-wife sign a prenuptial agreement waiving
all her rights to inherit under his will.
192
Following the husband’s death,
the wife sought to void the agreement on grounds of substantive
fairness.
193
The court rejected her challenge, finding that the waiver was
part of a typical prenuptial agreement, often included where spouses
seek to protect the inheritance rights of children from a previous
marriage.
194
Thus, nothing about the agreement was unforeseen so as to
prevent its enforcement on substantive fairness grounds.
Newman v. Newman
195
is another case where the court denied the
wife’s request to void a waiver of maintenance at the time of
enforcement upon finding that intervening circumstances were not
unforeseen. On the contrary, at the time the prenuptial agreement was
executed, the parties contemplated that the wife would complete her
education so that she could work as an accountant, which is exactly
what transpired.
196
Thus, even though the husband had considerable
wealth and the wife was earning only $1500 per month at the time of
their divorce, the court did not find the maintenance waiver to be
unconscionable, because the parties’ expectations during the marriage
had been met.
197
By contrast, in Martin v. Farber,
198
the court was influenced by the
wife’s disingenuity during the forty-four year marriage and decided to
impose a constructive trust on the wife’s property in favor of her
husband, notwithstanding the fact that the husband had waived his right
to all the wife’s property acquired before and during the marriage in a
prenuptial agreement. Throughout their marriage, the husband was the
sole wage earner, consistently turning over money to the wife who, in
turn, promised to take care of him with those funds.
199
Instead, she used
191
Pajak v. Pajak, 385 S.E.2d 384, 387 (W. Va. 1989).
192
Id. at 385.
193
The court was not persuaded by wife’s argument that the prenuptial agreement was
procedurally unfair, finding that “there is no evidence that [the husband] was at all secretive or
in any way misled [the wife].” Id. at 388.
194
Id. at 38788 (observing that the provision was part of “a traditional pre-nuptial
agreement designed to protect the inheritance rights of children from claims made by a new
wife who is not the children’s mother”).
195
Newman v. Newman, 653 P.2d 728 (Colo. 1982) (en banc).
196
Id. at 736.
197
Id.
198
Martin v. Farber, 510 A.2d 608 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1986).
199
Id. at 612.
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1909
the money to acquire assets in her own name.
200
The court recognized
the substantive unfairness that would result to the husband if it were to
enforce the prenuptial agreement in light of the wife’s unexpected
intervening bad behavior.
201
Thus, the court imposed a constructive
trust in favor of the husband on assets in the wife’s estate that could be
traced back to being purchased with money he provided.
202
In this
manner, the court assured substantive fairness by protecting against
unforeseen developments that would have made enforcement of the
original contract shockingly unfair.
2. The Ramifications of Intervening Events Are Likewise a Key
Factor for Courts in Determining Whether a Surrogacy Contract Is
Substantively Fair
As with prenuptial agreements, intervening events are relevant to
courts determining whether a challenged surrogacy agreement is
substantively fair.
203
In a case involving breach of such a contract,
relevant changed circumstances include those that impact either the
surrogate’s consent or the environment into which the child will be
placed.
204
A deterioration in the relationship during the pregnancy
between the surrogate and the intended parents is an example of an
intervening event that affects informed consent to the extent a provision
in the gestational contract permitting the surrogate to remain a part of
the child’s life is frustrated.
205
Likewise, the surrogate’s purpose to
surrender the child to an intact family might be frustrated if the
intended parents have separated or are no longer able to provide for the
child financially.
206
Thus, to assure that a surrogacy contract is substantively fair in
light of intervening events, some courts will not automatically accept the
parties’ predetermined conclusion that the best interests of the child are
200
Id.
201
Id.
202
Id.; see also Gross v. Gross, 464 N.E.2d 500 (Ohio 1984) (finding an alimony provision by
which maximum payment to wife was $200 per month unconscionable at enforcement, as this
amount would result in an extreme lifestyle change from the unforeseeable opulent standard of
living during the marriage).
203
Lewis, supra note 126, at 948 (“In a surrogacy contract dispute, the only changed
circumstances that are relevant are those that impact the surrogate’s ability to give informed
consent and the child’s opportunity to be placed in the best living environment.”).
204
Id.
205
Id.
206
See id.; see also In re Marriage of Moschetta, 25 Cal. App. 4th 1218, 1223 (Ct. App. 1994)
(discussing how the traditional surrogate began to reconsider the adoption post-delivery after
learning while in labor that the intended parents had separated).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1910 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
furthered by placement with the intended parents.
207
Rather, these
courts conduct a de novo review,
208
using the provisions of the parental
scheme in the surrogacy contract as a guide for determining the child’s
best interests.
209
In this way, maximum effect is given to the parties’
intentions by enforcing a surrogacy arrangement as agreed, provided
that intervening events have not resulted in circumstances that require
modification to assure substantive fairness.
210
To the extent this model
has succeeded in the realm of some form of ante-natal contract, that is,
both the prenuptial and surrogacy agreements, one has reason for
encouragement that such a scheme befits another form of ante-natal
contract, that is, those pertaining to disposition of frozen pre-embryos.
IV.
PROPOSAL
A. Predisposition Contracts Should Be Separate from Informed
Consent Forms to Assure Procedural Fairness
Courts tasked with deciding whether or not to enforce a
predisposition contract in a divorce proceeding should assure
procedural fairness with reference to the safeguards of full disclosure
and voluntariness required to enforce a prenuptial or surrogacy
agreement. To assure that directives pertaining to a frozen pre-embryo
are based on full disclosure, courts should require that these provisions
be set forth in an agreement that is separate and distinct from the form
that the medical provider uses to obtain informed consent prior to IVF.
One option for creating such a contract is to provide for
disposition of pre-embryos in the prenuptial agreement itself. The
courts have not yet squarely addressed whether such a provision would
be valid.
211
However, both the UPAA and UPMAA support this
207
See In re Baby, 447 S.W.3d 807, 828 (Tenn. 2014) (“[C]ourts are not bound by any
surrogacy contract as to the determination of the best interests of a child.”).
208
Indeed, such review is not necessarily limited to instances where one party opts not to
perform a gestational contract post-delivery. Some states require the court validation of a
surrogacy contract as a condition precedent to the adoption. See, e.g., U
TAH CODE ANN.
§§ 78B-15-801(4), -803 (West 2009).
209
See, e.g., In re Baby, 447 S.W.3d at 829 (“In most instances, enforcing the parenting
scheme as provided by a surrogacy contract will support the best interests of the child.”); In re
F.T.R., 2013 WI 66, ¶ 61, 349 Wis. 2d 84, 116, 833 N.W.2d 634, 64950 (“Enforcement of
surrogacy agreements promotes stability and permanence in family relationships because it
allows the intended parents to plan for the arrival of their child . . . and reduces contentious
litigation that could drag on for the first several years of the child’s life.”).
210
See supra Section III.C.2.
211
In Dahl v. Angle, 194 P.3d 834, 840 (Or. Ct. App. 2008), however, the court recognized
the congruence of these two contracts, stating that “giving effect to a valid agreement evincing
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1911
possibility by allowing the parties to determine any personal right, so
long as their arrangement does not violate public policy.
212
Thus,
provisions as to frozen pre-embryos in a prenuptial agreement would
comport with both these Acts, as some courts have recognized that
predisposition contracts actually promote public policy in favor of
procreative liberty.
213
Furthermore, including provisions for disposition of frozen pre-
embryos is consistent with the aim of a prenuptial agreement to
determine the parties’ rights and obligations in property no matter
where located or how acquired.
214
In light of the case law confirming
that pre-embryos are property, albeit entitled to “special respect,”
215
providing for their disposition along with other types of ownership
interests upon divorce appears reasonable.
216
The fact that provisions in a prenuptial agreement limiting child
support, visitation, and custody rights are void
217
should not impede
inclusion of predisposition arrangements, as pre-embryos are
distinguishable from live children. As the court in Davis reviewed, a
four- to eight-cell pre-embryo is far removed, both quantitatively and
the parties’ intent regarding disposition of embryos is consistent with our statutory and case
law that give similar effect to prenuptial agreements.”
212
See, e.g., UNIF. PREMARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 3(a)(6) (UNIF. LAW COMMN 1983); see
also U
NIF. PREMARITAL & MARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 10 cmt. (UNIF. LAW COMMN 2012)
(“[O]ther provisions which are contrary to public policy would also be unenforceable.”). The
National Conference of Commissioners for Uniform State Laws, also known as the Uniform
Law Commission, drafted both the UPAA and the UPMAA. This Commission provides states
with non-partisan legislation to bring stability to important areas of state statutory law. The
UPAA has been adopted by twenty-six jurisdictions, half of which made significant changes.
The Commission passed the UPMAA in 2012 to address some of the concerns with the UPAA.
To date, only Colorado and North Carolina have adopted the UPMAA, though the Act is
pending consideration in Mississippi. See Premarital and Marital Agreements Act, U
NIF. LAW
COMMN, http://www.uniformlaws.org/Act.aspx?title=Premarital%20and%20Marital%
20Agreements%20Act (last visited Apr. 9, 2017).
213
See, e.g., Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 597 (Tenn. 1992) (noting that procreative liberty
is furthered by leaving full authority to the progenitors to decide the fate of frozen pre-embryos
based on privately held convictions about self-identifying as a genetic parent, and the point at
which life begins).
214
See UNIF. PREMARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 3(a)(1) (noting that prenuptial agreements
aim to address “the rights and obligations of each of the parties in any of the property of either
or both of them whenever and wherever acquired or located”); see also U
NIF. PREMARITAL &
MARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 2(6) (defining property as “anything that may be the subject of
ownership”).
215
See Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 597.
216
See also Sublett, supra note 37, at 596 (“Because the sperm and egg have united to
become one, the resulting concept cannot be said to be the personal property of either the male
or the female, but rather the marital property of both.”).
217
See, e.g., UNIF. PREMARITAL & MARITAL AGREEMENT ACT § 10(b) (providing that a term
in a premarital agreement is unenforceable “to the extent that it: (1) adversely affects a child’s
right to support”); see also Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131, 1141 (Pa. Super. Ct. 2012) (questioning
whether a party to a predisposition contract can waive support for the future child).
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1912 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
qualitatively, from viabilitythe point at which a fetus is assigned legal
rights.
218
Accordingly, provisions for the disposition of pre-embryos
would be consistent both with what a prenuptial agreement intends to
include, as well as with what it seeks to exclude.
Whether or not a couple about to marry will want to include a
provision that speaks to infertility in a pre-nuptial agreement is, of
course, debatable. The key point, however, is that such a provision could
be included in a prenuptial agreement if the parties so choose, and
would likely be enforced as within a procedurally and substantively fair
contract.
Removing the disposition language from the consent form and into
an agreement of its own, be it a prenuptial agreement or a contract
made at the time of IVF, will focus the spouses on the issue of unused
pre-embryos. Such focus will, thereby, foster the private discussion that
is needed in order to make a knowing contingency plan in the event of
divorce.
219
In particular, the spouses would have the opportunity to
communicate candidly with each other and share their respective
feelings about the genetic connection to a child they might not raise, the
inception of life, and raising a child in a family that is not intact.
220
Full
disclosure and contemplation of these issues would obviate the criticism
that predisposition contracts may not reflect the spouses’ actual
intentions,
221
as procedural safeguards would be in place to assure the
terms were based upon frank information. Concomitantly, removing
the dispositional language from the informed consent realm would
assure voluntariness that is otherwise questionable in contracts set forth
on a standardized form, presented on a take-it-or-leave-it basis, and
with key provisions hidden in the fine print.
222
218
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 595 (stating viability is the critical point for assigning legal rights to
a fetus, and “[t]hat stage of fetal developmental is far removed, both qualitatively and
quantitatively, from that of the four-to eight-cell pre[-]embryos in this case”).
219
But see Kass v. Kass, 91 N.Y.2d 554, 566 (1998) (recognizing that neither party disputed
that the consent form was “an expression of their own intent regarding disposition of their pre-
zygotes,” nor did they dispute that their agreement was “freely and knowingly made”).
220
See Szafranski v. Dunston, 2013 IL App (1st) 122975, 41 (reasoning that its decision to
honor a predisposition agreement will “promote serious discussions between the parties prior
to participating in in vitro fertilization regarding their desires, intentions, and concerns”). Such
discussion could also include disposition preferences should one party have a change of heart
about parenthood due to future intervening events. Id. (“[T]he concern that individuals may
change their minds regarding parenthood . . . [and] not[ing] that this concern can be
adequately addressed in a contract and should be discussed in advance of the procedure.”).
221
See supra Section I.B.; see also Fleming, supra note 12, at 372 (“The process of executing a
contractual agreement to regulate future control of frozen embryos may also have the added
benefit of causing the parties to pause, think, and recognize the importance of the commitment
into which they are about to enter.”).
222
Waldman, supra note 120, at 926 (citing Res. Mgmt. Co. v. Weston Ranch, 706 P.2d
1028, 1042 (Utah 1985) (listing the hallmarks of procedural unconscionability as: the use of
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
2017] PRE- EMBRYO CUSTODY BATTLES 1913
Furthermore, courts should enforce a predisposition contract in
instances where the divorcing spouses have had the opportunity to seek
independent counsel. While retaining separate counsel may seem
misplaced as between a married couple endeavoring to start a family,
courts should at a minimum confirm that the parties have had the
chance to speak with an attorney for guidance about the dispositional
choices in the event of divorce. Adapting this safeguard to the formation
of predisposition contracts would assure that the preferred approach
223
for resolving disputes about the fate of frozen pre-embryos in a divorce
proceeding is procedurally fair.
B. Predisposition Contracts Should Consider Biological Realities to
Assure Substantive Fairness
As applied to predisposition contracts, courts may need to shift
their focus from unforeseen intervening circumstances to the biological
realities attendant with IVF to determine substantive fairness. As the
Davis court recognized, the possibility is quite real that one of the
parties participating in IVF may have no other reasonable means to
achieve genetic parenthood absent an award of the frozen pre-embryos
at the time of divorce.
224
Because men are physically able to procreate
longer than women, the wife in a divorce dispute about frozen pre-
embryos is more likely to be the spouse at risk of losing the chance to
become a biological parent.
225
Yet, if the predisposition contract is fairly procured,
226
the parties
will have discussed the physical realities that hinder the woman absent
the option of being awarded the frozen pre-embryos on a unilateral
basis. Indeed, such discussion would address concerns about future
parenthood and, thereby, obviate the criticism that the predisposition
approach fails to provide spouses with the opportunity to address this
topic.
227
Perhaps the courts would no longer need to consider the
boilerplate forms, offered on an as-is basis, and burying key terms in a morass of small print));
see also supra Section III.C.; supra note 78.
223
See supra Section I.B.
224
Davis v. Davis, 842 S.W.2d 588, 604 (Tenn. 1992); see also J.B. v. M.B., 783 A.2d 707, 720
(N.J. 2001) (specifically expressing “no opinion in respect of a case in which a party who has
become infertile seeks use of stored pre[-]embryos against the wishes of his or her partner”);
Reber v. Reiss, 42 A.3d 1131 (Pa. Super. Ct. 2012); supra note 49.
225
Waldman, supra note 120, at 928.
226
See supra Section IV.A.
227
See supra Parts IIIII; see also Fleming, supra note 12, at 372 (“[C]hanged circumstances
in embryo dispute cases are no different from the changed circumstances that could occur in
many other contractual situations that do not render contracts unenforceable. Therefore,
ALENICK.38.5.6 (Do Not Delete) 6/2/2017 3:18 PM
1914 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1879
applicability of the Davis exception
228
if the parties themselves enter into
a predisposition contract following their discussion that cryopreserved
pre-embryos might be the wife’s last chance to become a genetic parent.
A woman’s choice to forgo use of her own pre-embryos is not troubling
so long as such choice is procedurally and substantively fair.
229
Courts
should, therefore, enforce a predisposition agreement between divorcing
spouses that meets these fairness standards.
C
ONCLUSION
Predisposition agreements are the best model for determining the
fate of frozen pre-embryos so long as safeguards are in place to assure
procedural and substantive fairness. The solution to resolving the
inconsistent judicial response in divorce proceedings involving frozen
pre-embryos may, indeed, lie in the realm of prenuptial and surrogacy
agreements. By expanding the fairness standards already imposed just a
bit further to validate these other forms of ante-natal contracts, courts
may well find the winning solution that will enable a just resolution to
this recurring, if not escalating, issue.
holding parties to prior agreements despite changed circumstances is not unfair, unless either
party did not knowingly and freely enter into such agreement.” (footnote omitted)).
228
Davis, 842 S.W.2d at 604.
229
Waldman, supra note 120, at 929 (“A woman’s choice to erect a barrier to her own use of
the embryos post-divorce is untroubling if it indeed represents a choice.”).