1
W
hen writer Lewis Carroll took Alice
on her journeys down the rabbit hole to
Wonderland and through the looking
glass, she had many fantastic
encounters with the tea-sipping Mad
Hatter, a hookah-smoking Caterpillar, the
White Rabbit, the Cheshire Cat, the Red
and White Queens, and Tweedledum and
Tweedledee. On the surface, Carroll’s
writings seem to be delightful nonsense
and mere children’s entertainment. Many
people are quite surprised to learn that
Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland is as
much an exercise in logic as it is a fantasy
and that Lewis Carroll was actually
Charles Dodgson, an Oxford
mathematician. Dodgson’s many writings
include the whimsical The Game of Logic
and the brilliant Symbolic Logic, in
addition to Alice’s Adventures in
Wonderland and Through the Looking
Glass.
WHAT WE WILL DO In This Chapter
WE’LL EXPLORE DIFFERENT TYPES OF LOGIC OR
REASONING:
Deductive reasoning involves the application of a
general statement to a specific case; this type of
logic is typified in the classic arguments of the
renowned Greek logician Aristotle.
Inductive reasoning involves generalizing after a
pattern has been recognized and established; this
type of logic is used in the solving of puzzles.
WE’LL ANALYZE AND EXPLORE VARIOUS TYPES
OF STATEMENTS AND THE CONDITIONS UNDER
WHICH THEY ARE TRUE:
A statement is a simple sentence that is either true
or false. Simple statements can be connected to
form compound, or more complicated, statements.
Symbolic representations reduce a compound
statement to its basic form; phrases that appear to
be different may actually have the same basic
structure and meaning.
continued
1
© Bart Sadowski/iStockPhoto
Logic
continued
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 1
Property
and White Queens, and Tweedledum and
Property
and White Queens, and Tweedledum and
Tweedledee. On the surface, Carroll’s
Property
Tweedledee. On the surface, Carroll’s
writings seem to be delightful nonsense
Property
writings seem to be delightful nonsense
and mere children’s entertainment. Many
Property
and mere children’s entertainment. Many
people are quite surprised to learn that
Property
people are quite surprised to learn that
Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland
Property
Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland
much an exercise in logic as it is a fantasy
Property
much an exercise in logic as it is a fantasy
and that Lewis Carroll was actually
Property
and that Lewis Carroll was actually
of
Hatter, a hookah-smoking Caterpillar, the
of
Hatter, a hookah-smoking Caterpillar, the
White Rabbit, the Cheshire Cat, the Red
of
White Rabbit, the Cheshire Cat, the Red
and White Queens, and Tweedledum and
of
and White Queens, and Tweedledum and
Tweedledee. On the surface, Carroll’s
of
Tweedledee. On the surface, Carroll’s
Cengage
W
Cengage
W
Cengage
Hatter, a hookah-smoking Caterpillar, the
Cengage
Hatter, a hookah-smoking Caterpillar, the
Cengage
Learning
WHAT WE WILL DO In This Chapter continued
WE’LL ANALYZE AND EXPLORE CONDITIONAL, OR “IF . . . THEN . . .,”
STATEMENTS:
In everyday conversation, we often connect phrases by saying “if this, then
that.” However, does “this” actually guarantee “that? Is “this” in fact
necessary for “that?
How does “if” compare with “only if”? What does “if and only if” really
mean?
WE’LL DETERMINE THE VALIDITY OF AN ARGUMENT:
What constitutes a valid argument? Can a valid argument yield a false
conclusion?
You may have used Venn diagrams to depict a solution set in an algebra
class. We will use Venn diagrams to visualize and analyze an argument.
Some of Lewis Carroll’s whimsical arguments are valid, and some are not.
How can you tell?
Webster’s New World College Dictionary defines logic as “the
science of correct reasoning; science which describes relationships among
propositions in terms of implication, contradiction, contrariety, conversion,
etc.” In addition to being flaunted in Mr. Spock’s claim that “your human
emotions have drawn you to an illogical conclusion” and in Sherlock
Holmes’s immortal phrase “elementary, my dear Watson,” logic is
fundamental both to critical thinking and to problem solving. In today’s
world of misleading commercial claims, innuendo, and political rhetoric,
the ability to distinguish between valid and invalid arguments is
important.
In this chapter, we will study the basic components of logic and its
application. Mischievous, wild-eyed residents of Wonderland, eccentric,
violin-playing detectives, and cold, emotionless Vulcans are not the only
ones who can benefit from logic. Armed with the fundamentals of logic, we
can surely join Spock and “live long and prosper!”
2
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 2
Property
emotions have drawn you to an illogical conclusion” and in Sherlock
Property
emotions have drawn you to an illogical conclusion” and in Sherlock
Holmes’s immortal phrase “elementary, my dear Watson,” logic is
Property
Holmes’s immortal phrase “elementary, my dear Watson,” logic is
fundamental both to critical thinking and to problem solving. In today’s
Property
fundamental both to critical thinking and to problem solving. In today’s
world of misleading commercial claims, innuendo, and political rhetoric,
Property
world of misleading commercial claims, innuendo, and political rhetoric,
the ability to distinguish between valid and invalid arguments is
Property
the ability to distinguish between valid and invalid arguments is
important.
Property
important.
application. Mischievous, wild-eyed residents of Wonderland, eccentric,
Property
application. Mischievous, wild-eyed residents of Wonderland, eccentric,
of
propositions in terms of implication, contradiction, contrariety, conversion,
of
propositions in terms of implication, contradiction, contrariety, conversion,
etc.” In addition to being flaunted in Mr. Spock’s claim that “your human
of
etc.” In addition to being flaunted in Mr. Spock’s claim that “your human
emotions have drawn you to an illogical conclusion” and in Sherlock
of
emotions have drawn you to an illogical conclusion” and in Sherlock
Holmes’s immortal phrase “elementary, my dear Watson,” logic is
of
Holmes’s immortal phrase “elementary, my dear Watson,” logic is
Cengage
Cengage
Webster’s New World College Dictionary
Cengage
Webster’s New World College Dictionary
science of correct reasoning; science which describes relationships among
Cengage
science of correct reasoning; science which describes relationships among
propositions in terms of implication, contradiction, contrariety, conversion,
Cengage
propositions in terms of implication, contradiction, contrariety, conversion,
etc.” In addition to being flaunted in Mr. Spock’s claim that “your human
Cengage
etc.” In addition to being flaunted in Mr. Spock’s claim that “your human
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
Can a valid argument yield a false
Learning
Can a valid argument yield a false
You may have used Venn diagrams to depict a solution set in an algebra
Learning
You may have used Venn diagrams to depict a solution set in an algebra
class. We will use Venn diagrams to visualize and analyze an argument.
Learning
class. We will use Venn diagrams to visualize and analyze an argument.
Some of Lewis Carroll’s whimsical arguments are valid, and some are not.
Learning
Some of Lewis Carroll’s whimsical arguments are valid, and some are not.
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 3
Logic is the science of correct reasoning.
Auguste Rodin captured this ideal in his
bronze sculpture The Thinker.
In their quest for logical perfection, the
Vulcans of Star Trek abandoned all emotion.
Mr. Spock’s frequent proclamation that
“emotions are illogical” typified this attitude.
Vanni/Art Resource, NY
PARAMOUNT TELEVISION/THE KOBAL COLLECTION
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning
O
bjectives
Use Venn diagrams to determine the validity of deductive arguments
Use inductive reasoning to predict patterns
Logic is the science of correct reasoning. Webster’s New World College Dictionary
defines reasoning as “the drawing of inferences or conclusions from known or
assumed facts.” Reasoning is an integral part of our daily lives; we take appropriate
actions based on our perceptions and experiences. For instance, if the sky is heav-
ily overcast this morning, you might assume that it will rain today and take your
umbrella when you leave the house.
Problem Solving
Logic and reasoning are associated with the phrases problem solving and critical
thinking. If we are faced with a problem, puzzle, or dilemma, we attempt to reason
through it in hopes of arriving at a solution.
The first step in solving any problem is to define the problem in a thorough
and accurate manner. Although this might sound like an obvious step, it is often
overlooked. Always ask yourself, “What am I being asked to do?” Before you can
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 3
Property
bjectives
Property
bjectives
Use Venn diagrams to determine the validity of deductive arguments
Property
Use Venn diagrams to determine the validity of deductive arguments
Use inductive reasoning to predict patterns
Property
Use inductive reasoning to predict patterns
of
of
Cengage
Cengage
Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning
Cengage
Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning
Learning
Learning
In their quest for logical perfection, the
Learning
In their quest for logical perfection, the
Vulcans of
Learning
Vulcans of
Mr. Spock’s frequent proclamation that
Learning
Mr. Spock’s frequent proclamation that
“emotions are illogical” typified this attitude.
Learning
“emotions are illogical” typified this attitude.
solve a problem, you must understand the question. Once the problem has been
defined, all known information that is relevant to it must be gathered, organized,
and analyzed. This analysis should include a comparison of the present problem to
previous ones. How is it similar? How is it different? Does a previous method of
solution apply? If it seems appropriate, draw a picture of the problem; visual
representations often provide insight into the interpretation of clues.
Before using any specific formula or method of solution, determine whether
its use is valid for the situation at hand. A common error is to use a formula or
method of solution when it does not apply. If a past formula or method of solution
is appropriate, use it; if not, explore standard options and develop creative alterna-
tives. Do not be afraid to try something different or out of the ordinary. “What if I
try this . . . ?” may lead to a unique solution.
Deductive Reasoning
Once a problem has been defined and analyzed, it might fall into a known category
of problems, so a common method of solution may be applied. For instance, when
one is asked to solve the equation x
2
2x 1, realizing that it is a second-degree
equation (that is, a quadratic equation) leads one to put it into the standard
form (x
2
2x 1 0) and apply the Quadratic Formula.
EXAMPLE 1 USING DEDUCTIVE REASONING TO SOLVE AN EQUATION Solve the
equation x
2
2x 1.
SOLUTION The given equation is a second-degree equation in one variable. We know that all
second-degree equations in one variable (in the form ax
2
bx c 0) can be
solved by applying the Quadratic Formula:
x
b ; 2b
2
4ac
2a
4 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Using his extraordinary powers of logical deduction, Sherlock Holmes
solves another mystery. “Finding the villain was elementary, my dear
Watson.”
AVCO EMBASSY/THE KOBAL COLLECTION
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 4
Property
Property
tives. Do not be
Property
tives. Do not be
try this . . . ?” may lead to a unique solution.
Property
try this . . . ?” may lead to a unique solution.
Deductive Reasoning
Property
Deductive Reasoning
of
method of solution when it does not apply. If a past formula or method of solution
of
method of solution when it does not apply. If a past formula or method of solution
is appropriate, use it; if not, explore standard options and develop creative alterna-
of
is appropriate, use it; if not, explore standard options and develop creative alterna-
tives. Do not be
of
tives. Do not be
afraid to try something different or out of the ordinary. “What if I
of
afraid to try something different or out of the ordinary. “What if I
try this . . . ?” may lead to a unique solution.
of
try this . . . ?” may lead to a unique solution.
Cengage
solve a problem, you must understand the question. Once the problem has been
Cengage
solve a problem, you must understand the question. Once the problem has been
defined, all known information that is relevant to it must be gathered, organized,
Cengage
defined, all known information that is relevant to it must be gathered, organized,
and analyzed. This analysis should include a comparison of the present problem to
Cengage
and analyzed. This analysis should include a comparison of the present problem to
previous ones. How is it similar? How is it different? Does a previous method of
Cengage
previous ones. How is it similar? How is it different? Does a previous method of
solution apply? If it seems appropriate, draw a picture of the problem; visual
Cengage
solution apply? If it seems appropriate, draw a picture of the problem; visual
representations often provide insight into the interpretation of clues.
Cengage
representations often provide insight into the interpretation of clues.
Before using any specific formula or method of solution, determine whether
Cengage
Before using any specific formula or method of solution, determine whether
its use is valid for the situation at hand. A common error is to use a formula or
Cengage
its use is valid for the situation at hand. A common error is to use a formula or
method of solution when it does not apply. If a past formula or method of solution
Cengage
method of solution when it does not apply. If a past formula or method of solution
is appropriate, use it; if not, explore standard options and develop creative alterna-
Cengage
is appropriate, use it; if not, explore standard options and develop creative alterna-
Learning
Learning
Learning
Using his extraordinary powers of logical deduction, Sherlock
Learning
Using his extraordinary powers of logical deduction, Sherlock
Holmes
Learning
Holmes
solves another mystery. “Finding the villain was elementary,
Learning
solves another mystery. “Finding the villain was elementary,
my dear
Learning
my dear
AVCO EMBASSY/THE KOBAL COLLECTION
Learning
AVCO EMBASSY/THE KOBAL COLLECTION
Therefore, x
2
2x 1 can be solved by applying the Quadratic Formula:
The solutions are
In Example 1, we applied a general rule to a specific case; we reasoned that
it was valid to apply the (general) Quadratic Formula to the (specific) equation
x
2
2x 1. This type of logic is known as deductive reasoning—that is, the
application of a general statement to a specific instance.
Deductive reasoning and the formal structure of logic have been studied for
thousands of years. One of the earliest logicians, and one of the most renowned,
was Aristotle (384–322
B.C.). He was the student of the great philosopher Plato and
the tutor of Alexander the Great, the conqueror of all the land from Greece to
India. Aristotle’s philosophy is pervasive; it influenced Roman Catholic theology
through St. Thomas Aquinas and continues to influence modern philosophy. For
centuries, Aristotelian logic was part of the education of lawyers and politicians
and was used to distinguish valid arguments from invalid ones.
For Aristotle, logic was the necessary tool for any inquiry, and the syllogism
was the sequence followed by all logical thought. Asyllogism is an argument com-
posed of two statements, or premises (the major and minor premises), followed by
a conclusion. For any given set of premises, if the conclusion of an argument is
guaranteed (that is, if it is inescapable in all instances), the argument is valid. If the
conclusion is not guaranteed (that is, if there is at least one instance in which it
does not follow), the argument is invalid.
Perhaps the best known of Aristotle’s syllogisms is the following:
1. All men are mortal. major premise
2. Socrates is a man. minor premise
Therefore, Socrates is mortal. conclusion
When the major premise is applied to the minor premise, the conclusion is
inescapable; the argument is valid.
Notice that the deductive reasoning used in the analysis of Example 1 has
exactly the same structure as Aristotle’s syllogism concerning Socrates:
1. All second-degree equations in one variable can be major premise
solved by applying the Quadratic Formula.
2. x
2
2x 1 is a second-degree equation in one variable. minor premise
Therefore, x
2
2x 1 can be solved by applying the conclusion
Quadratic Formula.
x 1 22
and x 1 22.
x 1 ; 22
x
211 ; 22
2
2
x
2 ; 222
2
x
2 ; 28
2
x
2 ; 24 4
2
x
122 ; 2122
2
1421112
2112
x
2
2x 1 0
x
2
2x 1
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 5
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 5
Property
centuries, Aristotelian logic was part of the education of lawyers and politicians
Property
centuries, Aristotelian logic was part of the education of lawyers and politicians
and was used to distinguish valid arguments from invalid ones.
Property
and was used to distinguish valid arguments from invalid ones.
For Aristotle, logic was the necessary tool for any inquiry, and the syllogism
Property
For Aristotle, logic was the necessary tool for any inquiry, and the syllogism
was the sequence followed by all logical thought. A
Property
was the sequence followed by all logical thought. A
posed of two statements, or
Property
posed of two statements, or
of
the tutor of Alexander the Great, the conqueror of all the land from Greece to
of
the tutor of Alexander the Great, the conqueror of all the land from Greece to
India. Aristotle’s philosophy is pervasive; it influenced Roman Catholic theology
of
India. Aristotle’s philosophy is pervasive; it influenced Roman Catholic theology
through St. Thomas Aquinas and continues to influence modern philosophy. For
of
through St. Thomas Aquinas and continues to influence modern philosophy. For
centuries, Aristotelian logic was part of the education of lawyers and politicians
of
centuries, Aristotelian logic was part of the education of lawyers and politicians
Cengage
In Example 1, we applied a general rule to a specific case; we reasoned that
Cengage
In Example 1, we applied a general rule to a specific case; we reasoned that
it was valid to apply the (general) Quadratic Formula to the (specific) equation
Cengage
it was valid to apply the (general) Quadratic Formula to the (specific) equation
1. This type of logic is known as
Cengage
1. This type of logic is known as
application of a general statement to a specific instance.
Cengage
application of a general statement to a specific instance.
Deductive reasoning and the formal structure of logic have been studied for
Cengage
Deductive reasoning and the formal structure of logic have been studied for
thousands of years. One of the earliest logicians, and one of the most renowned,
Cengage
thousands of years. One of the earliest logicians, and one of the most renowned,
was Aristotle (384–322
Cengage
was Aristotle (384–322
the tutor of Alexander the Great, the conqueror of all the land from Greece to
Cengage
the tutor of Alexander the Great, the conqueror of all the land from Greece to
India. Aristotle’s philosophy is pervasive; it influenced Roman Catholic theology
Cengage
India. Aristotle’s philosophy is pervasive; it influenced Roman Catholic theology
Learning
and
Learning
and
x
Learning
x
Learning
1
Learning
1
Learning
6 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Each of these syllogisms is of the following general form:
1. If A, then B. All A are B. (major premise)
2. x is A. We have A. (minor premise)
Therefore, x is B. Therefore, we have B. (conclusion)
Historically, this valid pattern of deductive reasoning is known as modus ponens.
Deductive Reasoning and Venn Diagrams
The validity of a deductive argument can be shown by use of a Venn diagram. A
Venn diagram is a diagram consisting of various overlapping figures contained
within a rectangle (called the “universe”). To depict a statement of the form “All
A are B” (or, equivalently, “If A, then B”), we draw two circles, one inside the
other; the inner circle represents A, and the outer circle represents B. This rela-
tionship is shown in Figure 1.1.
Venn diagrams depicting “No A are B” and “Some A are B” are shown in Fig-
ures 1.2 and 1.3, respectively.
U
A
B
All A are B. (If A, then B.)
FIGURE 1.1
U
A
B
U
A
B
No A are B.
FIGURE 1.2
Some A are B. (At least one A is B.)FIGURE 1.3
EXAMPLE 2 ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT Construct a Venn diagram to
verify the validity of the following argument:
1. All men are mortal.
2. Socrates is a man.
Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
SOLUTION Premise 1 is of the form “All A are B” and can be represented by a diagram like that
shown in Figure 1.4.
Premise 2 refers to a specific man, namely, Socrates. If we let x Socrates,
the statement “Socrates is a man” can then be represented by placing x within the
circle labeled “men,” as shown in Figure 1.5. Because we placed x within the
“men” circle, and all of the “men” circle is inside the “mortal” circle, the conclu-
sion “Socrates is mortal” is inescapable; the argument is valid.
U
men
mortal
U
x
men
mortal
xSocrates
All men are mortal.
FIGURE 1.4
Socrates is mortal.FIGURE 1.5
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 6
Property
verify the validity of the following argument:
Property
verify the validity of the following argument:
1. All men are mortal.
Property
1. All men are mortal.
2. Socrates is a man.
Property
2. Socrates is a man.
Property
Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
Property
Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
Premise 1 is of the form “All
Property
Premise 1 is of the form “All
shown in Figure 1.4.
Property
shown in Figure 1.4.
Property
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
Property
of
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
of
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
verify the validity of the following argument:
of
verify the validity of the following argument:
1. All men are mortal.
of
1. All men are mortal.
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
A
Cengage
A
are
Cengage
are
B
Cengage
B
.
Cengage
.
Cengage
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
Cengage
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
Learning
within a rectangle (called the “universe”). To depict a statement of the form “All
Learning
within a rectangle (called the “universe”). To depict a statement of the form “All
”), we draw two circles, one inside the
Learning
”), we draw two circles, one inside the
and the outer circle represents
Learning
and the outer circle represents
B.
Learning
B.
” and “Some
Learning
” and “Some
A
Learning
A
are
Learning
are
B
Learning
B
” are shown in Fig-
Learning
” are shown in Fig-
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 7
supervise the educa-
tion of his son
Alexander, the future
Alexander the Great.
Aristotle accepted
the invitation and
taught Alexander
until he succeeded
his father as ruler. At
that time, Aristotle
founded a school
known as the
Lyceum, or Peripatetic School. The school
had a large library with many maps, as
well as botanical gardens containing an
extensive collection of plants and animals.
Aristotle and his students would walk
about the grounds of the Lyceum while dis-
cussing various subjects (peripatetic is
from the Greek word meaning “to walk”).
Many consider Aristotle to be a
founding father of the study of biology
and of science in general; he observed
and classified the behavior and
anatomy of hundreds of living creatures.
Alexander the Great, during his many
military campaigns, had his troops
gather specimens from distant places for
Aristotle to study.
Aristotle was a prolific writer; some
historians credit him with the writing of
over 1,000 books. Most of his works
have been lost or destroyed, but schol-
ars have recreated some of his more in-
fluential works, including Organon.
Historical
Note
Aristotle’s collective works on syllogisms and
deductive logic are known as Organon,
meaning “instrument,” for logic is the instrument
used in the acquisition of knowledge.
Collections of the New York Public Library
A
ristotle was born in
384
B.C. in the small
Macedonian town of Stagira,
200 miles north of Athens, on
the shore of the Aegean
Sea. Aristotle’s father was the
personal physician of King
Amyntas II, ruler of Macedo-
nia. When he was seventeen,
Aristotle enrolled at the Academy in
Athens and became a student of the
famed Plato.
Aristotle was one of Plato’s brightest
students; he frequently questioned Plato’s
teachings and openly disagreed with
him. Whereas Plato emphasized the
study of abstract ideas and mathematical
truth, Aristotle was more interested in
observing the “real world” around him.
Plato often referred to Aristotle as “the
brain” or “the mind of the school.” Plato
commented, “Where others need the
spur, Aristotle needs the rein.”
Aristotle stayed at the Academy for
twenty years, until the death of Plato. Then
the king of Macedonia invited Aristotle to
Museo Archaeologico Nazionale, Naples,
© Scala/Art Resource, NY
EXAMPLE 3 ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT Construct a Venn diagram to
determine the validity of the following argument:
1. All doctors are men.
2. My mother is a doctor.
Therefore, my mother is a man.
SOLUTION Premise 1 is of the form “All A are B”; the argument is depicted in Figure 1.6.
No matter where x is placed within the “doctors” circle, the conclusion “My
mother is a man” is inescapable; the argument is valid.
Saying that an argument is valid does not mean that the conclusion is true.
The argument given in Example 3 is valid, but the conclusion is false. One’s
mother cannot be a man! Validity and truth do not mean the same thing. An argu-
ment is valid if the conclusion is inescapable, given the premises. Nothing is said
about the truth of the premises. Thus, when examining the validity of an argument,
we are not determining whether the conclusion is true or false. Saying that an
argument is valid merely means that, given the premises, the reasoning used to
obtain the conclusion is logical. However, if the premises of a valid argument are
true, then the conclusion will also be true.
U
x
doctors
men
xMy mother
My mother is a man.
FIGURE 1.6
ARISTOTLE 384–322 B.C.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 7
Property
Property
EXAMPLE
Property
EXAMPLE
3
Property
3
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
Property
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
Property
of
gather specimens from distant places for
of
gather specimens from distant places for
Aristotle to study.
of
Aristotle to study.
of
Cengage
about the grounds of the Lyceum while dis-
Cengage
about the grounds of the Lyceum while dis-
cussing various subjects (
Cengage
cussing various subjects (
peripatetic
Cengage
peripatetic
from the Greek word meaning “to walk”).
Cengage
from the Greek word meaning “to walk”).
Many consider Aristotle to be a
Cengage
Many consider Aristotle to be a
founding father of the study of biology
Cengage
founding father of the study of biology
and of science in general; he observed
Cengage
and of science in general; he observed
and classified the behavior and
Cengage
and classified the behavior and
anatomy of hundreds of living creatures.
Cengage
anatomy of hundreds of living creatures.
Alexander the Great, during his many
Cengage
Alexander the Great, during his many
military campaigns, had his troops
Cengage
military campaigns, had his troops
gather specimens from distant places for
Cengage
gather specimens from distant places for
Aristotle to study.
Cengage
Aristotle to study.
Learning
well as botanical gardens containing an
Learning
well as botanical gardens containing an
extensive collection of plants and animals.
Learning
extensive collection of plants and animals.
Aristotle and his students would walk
Learning
Aristotle and his students would walk
about the grounds of the Lyceum while dis-
Learning
about the grounds of the Lyceum while dis-
peripatetic
Learning
peripatetic
is
Learning
is
Learning
If x is placed as in Figure 1.7, the argument would appear to be valid; the fig-
ure supports the conclusion “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” However, the
placement of x in Figure 1.8 does not support the conclusion; given the premises,
we cannot logically deduce that “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” Since the
conclusion is not inescapable, the argument is invalid.
Saying that an argument is invalid does not mean that the conclusion is false.
Example 4 demonstrates that an invalid argument can have a true conclusion; even
though The Rock is a professional wrestler, the argument used to obtain the con-
clusion is invalid. In logic, validity and truth do not have the same meaning.
Validity refers to the process of reasoning used to obtain a conclusion; truth refers
to conformity with fact or experience.
8 CHAPTER 1 Logic
actors
U
x = The Rock
professional
wrestlers
x
actors
U
x
x = The Rock
professional
wrestlers
FIGURE 1.7
FIGURE 1.8
EXAMPLE 4 ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT Construct a Venn diagram to
determine the validity of the following argument:
1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
2. The Rock is an actor.
Therefore, The Rock is a professional wrestler.
SOLUTION Premise 1 is of the form “All A are B”; the “circle of professional wrestlers” is con-
tained within the “circle of actors.” If we let x represent The Rock, premise 2 sim-
ply requires that we place x somewhere within the actor circle; x could be placed
in either of the two locations shown in Figures 1.7 and 1.8.
Even though The Rock is a
professional wrestler, the
argument used to obtain the
conclusion is invalid.
© Duomo/CORBIS
EXAMPLE 5 ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT Construct a Venn diagram to
determine the validity of the following argument:
1. Some plants are poisonous.
2. Broccoli is a plant.
Therefore, broccoli is poisonous.
VENN DIAGRAMS AND INVALID ARGUMENTS
To show that an argument is invalid, you must construct a Venn diagram in
which the premises are met yet the conclusion does not necessarily follow.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 8
Property
Saying that an argument is invalid does not mean that the conclusion is false.
Property
Saying that an argument is invalid does not mean that the conclusion is false.
Example 4 demonstrates that an invalid argument can have a true conclusion; even
Property
Example 4 demonstrates that an invalid argument can have a true conclusion; even
though The Rock is a professional wrestler, the argument used to obtain the con-
Property
though The Rock is a professional wrestler, the argument used to obtain the con-
clusion is invalid. In logic, validity and truth do not have the same meaning.
Property
clusion is invalid. In logic, validity and truth do not have the same meaning.
Validity
Property
Validity
to conformity with fact or experience.
Property
to conformity with fact or experience.
Property
© Duomo/CORBIS
Property
© Duomo/CORBIS
of
in Figure 1.8 does not support the conclusion; given the premises,
of
in Figure 1.8 does not support the conclusion; given the premises,
logically
of
logically
conclusion is
of
conclusion is
not
of
not
inescapable, the argument is invalid.
of
inescapable, the argument is invalid.
Cengage
is placed as in Figure 1.7, the argument would appear to be valid; the fig-
Cengage
is placed as in Figure 1.7, the argument would appear to be valid; the fig-
ure supports the conclusion “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” However, the
Cengage
ure supports the conclusion “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” However, the
in Figure 1.8 does not support the conclusion; given the premises,
Cengage
in Figure 1.8 does not support the conclusion; given the premises,
deduce that “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” Since the
Cengage
deduce that “The Rock is a professional wrestler.” Since the
Cengage
x
Cengage
x
Cengage
Cengage
FIGURE 1.8
Cengage
FIGURE 1.8
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
actors
Learning
actors
Learning
Learning
Learning
professional
Learning
professional
wrestlers
Learning
wrestlers
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 9
SOLUTION Premise 1 is of the form “Some A are B”; it can be represented by two overlapping
circles (as in Figure 1.3). If we let x represent broccoli, premise 2 requires that we
place x somewhere within the plant circle. If x is placed as in Figure 1.9, the argu-
ment would appear to be valid. However, if x is placed as in Figure 1.10, the con-
clusion does not follow. Because we can construct a Venn diagram in which the
premises are met yet the conclusion does not follow (Figure 1.10), the argument is
invalid.
plants
poison
U
x = broccoli
x
plants
poison
U
x = broccoli
x
FIGURE 1.9
FIGURE 1.10
When analyzing an argument via a Venn diagram, you might have to draw
three or more circles, as in the next example.
EXAMPLE 6 ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT Construct a Venn diagram to
determine the validity of the following argument:
1. No snake is warm-blooded.
2. All mammals are warm-blooded.
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
SOLUTION Premise 1 is of the form “No A are B”; it is depicted in Figure 1.11. Premise 2 is of
the form “All A are B”; the “mammal circle” must be drawn within the “warm-
blooded circle.” Both premises are depicted in Figure 1.12.
warm-blooded
snakes
U
mammals
snakes
warm-blooded
U
x = snake
x
No snake is warm-blooded.
FIGURE 1.11
All mammals are warm-blooded.FIGURE 1.12
Because we placed x ( snake) within the “snake” circle, and the “snake”
circle is outside the “warm-blooded” circle, x cannot be within the “mammal” circle
(which is inside the “warm-blooded” circle). Given the premises, the conclusion
“Snakes are not mammals” is inescapable; the argument is valid.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 9
Property
Property
Premise 1 is of the form “No
Property
Premise 1 is of the form “No
the form “All
Property
the form “All
blooded circle.” Both premises are depicted in Figure 1.12.
Property
blooded circle.” Both premises are depicted in Figure 1.12.
of
of
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
of
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
Premise 1 is of the form “No
of
Premise 1 is of the form “No
Cengage
When analyzing an argument via a Venn diagram, you might have to draw
Cengage
When analyzing an argument via a Venn diagram, you might have to draw
three or more circles, as in the next example.
Cengage
three or more circles, as in the next example.
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
Cengage
ANALYZING A DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
determine the validity of the following ar
Cengage
determine the validity of the following ar
1. No snake is warm-blooded.
Cengage
1. No snake is warm-blooded.
2. All mammals are warm-blooded.
Cengage
2. All mammals are warm-blooded.
Cengage
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
Cengage
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
poison
Learning
poison
broccoli
Learning
broccoli
Learning
FIGURE 1.10
Learning
FIGURE 1.10
When analyzing an argument via a Venn diagram, you might have to draw
Learning
When analyzing an argument via a Venn diagram, you might have to draw
three or more circles, as in the next example.
Learning
three or more circles, as in the next example.
You might have encountered Venn diagrams when you studied sets in your
algebra class. The academic fields of set theory and logic are historically inter-
twined; set theory was developed in the late nineteenth century as an aid in the
study of logical arguments. Today, set theory and Venn diagrams are applied to
areas other than the study of logical arguments; we will utilize Venn diagrams in
our general study of set theory in Chapter 2.
Inductive Reasoning
The conclusion of a valid deductive argument (one that goes from general to spe-
cific) is guaranteed: Given true premises, a true conclusion must follow. However,
there are arguments in which the conclusion is not guaranteed even though the
premises are true. Consider the following:
1. Joe sneezed after petting Frako’s cat.
2. Joe sneezed after petting Paulette’s cat.
Therefore, Joe is allergic to cats.
Is the conclusion guaranteed? If the premises are true, they certainly support the
conclusion, but we cannot say with 100% certainty that Joe is allergic to cats. The
conclusion is not guaranteed. Maybe Joe is allergic to the flea powder that the cat
owners used; maybe he is allergic to the dust that is trapped in the cats’ fur; or
maybe he has a cold!
Reasoning of this type is called inductive reasoning. Inductive reasoning
involvesgoing froma seriesof specificcases toa generalstatement (seeFigure 1.13).
Although it may seem to follow and may in fact be true, the conclusion in an in-
ductive argument is never guaranteed.
10 CHAPTER 1 Logic
general
specific
specific
general
Deductive Reasoning
(Conclusion is guaranteed.)
Inductive Reasoning
(Conclusion may be probable but is
not guaranteed.)
FIGURE 1.13
EXAMPLE 7 INDUCTIVE REASONING AND PATTERN RECOGNITION What is the
next number in the sequence 1, 8, 15, 22, 29, . . . ?
SOLUTION Noticing that the difference between consecutive numbers in the sequence is 7, we
may be tempted to say that the next term is 29 7 36. Is this conclusion guar-
anteed? No! Another sequence in which numbers differ by 7 are dates of a given
day of the week. For instance, the dates of the Saturdays in the year 2011 are
(January) 1, 8, 15, 22, 29, (February) 5, 12, 19, 26, . . . . Therefore, the next num-
ber in the sequence 1, 8, 15, 22, 29, . . . might be 5. Without further information,
we cannot determine the next number in the given sequence. We can only use
inductive reasoning and give one or more possible answers.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:32 AM Page 10
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
specific
Property
specific
Property
Property
of
of
of
general
of
general
Cengage
conclusion, but we cannot say with 100% certainty that Joe is allergic to cats. The
Cengage
conclusion, but we cannot say with 100% certainty that Joe is allergic to cats. The
guaranteed. Maybe Joe is allergic to the flea powder that the cat
Cengage
guaranteed. Maybe Joe is allergic to the flea powder that the cat
owners used; maybe he is allergic to the dust that is trapped in the cats’ fur; or
Cengage
owners used; maybe he is allergic to the dust that is trapped in the cats’ fur; or
Reasoning of this type is called inductive reasoning.
Cengage
Reasoning of this type is called inductive reasoning.
involvesgoing froma seriesof specificcases toa generalstatement (seeFigure 1.13).
Cengage
involvesgoing froma seriesof specificcases toa generalstatement (seeFigure 1.13).
Although it may seem to follow and may in fact be true,
Cengage
Although it may seem to follow and may in fact be true,
ductive argument is never guaranteed.
Cengage
ductive argument is never guaranteed.
Cengage
Learning
cific) is guaranteed: Given true premises, a true conclusion must follow. However,
Learning
cific) is guaranteed: Given true premises, a true conclusion must follow. However,
there are arguments in which the conclusion is not guaranteed even though the
Learning
there are arguments in which the conclusion is not guaranteed even though the
Is the conclusion guaranteed? If the premises are true, they certainly
Learning
Is the conclusion guaranteed? If the premises are true, they certainly
conclusion, but we cannot say with 100% certainty that Joe is allergic to cats. The
Learning
conclusion, but we cannot say with 100% certainty that Joe is allergic to cats. The
guaranteed. Maybe Joe is allergic to the flea powder that the cat
Learning
guaranteed. Maybe Joe is allergic to the flea powder that the cat
EXAMPLE 8 SOLVING A SUDOKU PUZZLE Solve the sudoku puzzle given in Figure 1.15.
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 11
T
hroughout history, people have al-
ways been attracted to puzzles,
mazes, and brainteasers. Who can
deny the inherent satisfaction of solving
a seemingly unsolvable or perplexing
riddle? A popular new addition to the
world of puzzle solving is sudoku, a
numbers puzzle. Loosely translated
from Japanese, sudoku means “single
number”; a sudoku puzzle simply in-
volves placing the digits 1 through 9 in
a grid containing 9 rows and
9 columns. In addition, the 9 by 9 grid
of squares is subdivided into nine 3 by
3 grids, or “boxes,” as shown in Fig-
ure 1.14.
The rules of sudoku are quite simple:
Each row, each column, and each box
must contain the digits 1 through 9; and
no row, column, or box can contain 2
squares with the same number. Conse-
quently, sudoku does not require any
arithmetic or mathematical skill; sudoku
requires logic only. In solving a puzzle, a
common thought is “What happens if I
put this number here?
Like crossword puzzles, sudoku puz-
zles are printed daily in many newspa-
pers across the country and around the
world. Web sites containing sudoku puz-
zles and strategies provide an endless
source of new puzzles and help. See
Exercise 62 to find links to popular sites.
Topic x
A blank sudoku grid.FIGURE 1.14
SUDOKU:
LOGIC IN THE REAL WORLD
2
8
3
3
6
7
8
6
4
9
8
6
1
4
6
5
7
2
4
5
1
9
8
9
1
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
A sudoku puzzle.
FIGURE 1.15
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 11
Property
Property
EXAMPLE
Property
EXAMPLE
8
Property
8
Property
Property
Property
FIGURE 1.14
Property
FIGURE 1.14
of
of
of
of
of
of
of
of
of
of
of
A blank sudoku grid.
of
A blank sudoku grid.
of
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
zles are printed
Learning
zles are printed
pers across the country and around the
Learning
pers across the country and around the
world. Web sites containing sudoku puz-
Learning
world. Web sites containing sudoku puz-
zles and strategies provide an endless
Learning
zles and strategies provide an endless
source of new puzzles and help. See
Learning
source of new puzzles and help. See
Exercise 62 to find links to popular sites.
Learning
Exercise 62 to find links to popular sites.
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
12 CHAPTER 1 Logic
123
456
789
2
6
1
123456789
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
8
7
Box numbers and coordinate system in sudoku.
FIGURE 1.16
2
6
8
3
3
6
7
8
6
4
9
8
6
1
4
6
5
7
2
4
5
1
9
8
9
1
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
The 6 in box 1 must be placed in square (3, 3).
FIGURE 1.17
Examining boxes 1, 2, and 3, we see that boxes 2 and 3 each contain the digit
5, whereas box 1 does not. We deduce that 5 must be placed in square (2, 3)
because rows 1 and 3 already have a 5. In a similar fashion, square (1, 4) must
contain 3. See Figure 1.18.
SOLUTION Recall that each 3 by 3 grid is referred to as a box. For convenience, the boxes are
numbered 1 through 9, starting in the upper left-hand corner and moving from left
to right, and each square can be assigned coordinates (x, y) based on its row num-
ber x and column number y as shown in Figure 1.16.
For example, the digit 2 in Figure 1.16 is in box 1 and has coordinates (1, 3), the
digit 8 is in box 3 and has coordinates (1, 7), the digit 6 is in box 4 and has coordi-
nates (5, 1) and the digit 7 is in box 9 and has coordinates (9, 7).
When you are first solving a sudoku puzzle, concentrate on only a few boxes
rather than the puzzle as a whole. For instance, looking at boxes 1, 4, and 7, we see
that boxes 4 and 7 each contain the digit 6, whereas box 1 does not. Consequently,
the 6 in box 1 must be placed in column 3 because (shaded) columns 1 and 2 al-
ready have a 6. However, (shaded) row 2 already has a 6, so we can deduce that 6
must be placed in row 3, column 3, that is, in square (3, 3) as shown in Figure 1.17.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 12
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
3
Property
3
Property
must be placed in row 3, column 3, that is, in square (3, 3) as shown in Figure 1.17.
Property
must be placed in row 3, column 3, that is, in square (3, 3) as shown in Figure 1.17.
of
that boxes 4 and 7 each contain the digit
of
that boxes 4 and 7 each contain the digit
in box 1 must be placed in column 3 because (shaded) columns 1 and 2 al-
of
in box 1 must be placed in column 3 because (shaded) columns 1 and 2 al-
ready have a
of
ready have a
6
of
6
. However, (shaded) row 2 already has a
of
. However, (shaded) row 2 already has a
must be placed in row 3, column 3, that is, in square (3, 3) as shown in Figure 1.17.
of
must be placed in row 3, column 3, that is, in square (3, 3) as shown in Figure 1.17.
Cengage
Box numbers and coordinate system in sudoku.
Cengage
Box numbers and coordinate system in sudoku.
Cengage
For example, the digit 2 in Figure 1.16 is in box 1 and has coordinates (1, 3), the
Cengage
For example, the digit 2 in Figure 1.16 is in box 1 and has coordinates (1, 3), the
digit 8 is in box 3 and has coordinates (1, 7), the digit 6 is in box 4 and has coordi-
Cengage
digit 8 is in box 3 and has coordinates (1, 7), the digit 6 is in box 4 and has coordi-
nates (5, 1) and the digit 7 is in box 9 and has coordinates (9, 7).
Cengage
nates (5, 1) and the digit 7 is in box 9 and has coordinates (9, 7).
When you are first solving a sudoku puzzle, concentrate on only a few boxes
Cengage
When you are first solving a sudoku puzzle, concentrate on only a few boxes
rather than the puzzle as a whole. For instance, looking at boxes 1, 4, and 7, we see
Cengage
rather than the puzzle as a whole. For instance, looking at boxes 1, 4, and 7, we see
that boxes 4 and 7 each contain the digit
Cengage
that boxes 4 and 7 each contain the digit
in box 1 must be placed in column 3 because (shaded) columns 1 and 2 al-
Cengage
in box 1 must be placed in column 3 because (shaded) columns 1 and 2 al-
. However, (shaded) row 2 already has a
Cengage
. However, (shaded) row 2 already has a
Learning
789
Learning
789
Learning
Learning
Learning
7
Learning
7
789
7
789
Learning
789
7
789
Box numbers and coordinate system in sudoku.
Learning
Box numbers and coordinate system in sudoku.
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 13
Because we have placed two new digits in box 1, we might wish to focus on
the remainder of (shaded) box 1. Notice that the digit 4 can be placed only in
square (3, 1), as row 1 and column 2 already have a 4 in each of them; likewise, the
digit 9 can be placed only in square (1, 1) because column 2 already has a 9.
Finally, either of the digits 1 or 7 can be placed in square (1, 2) or (3, 2) as shown
in Figure 1.19. At some point later in the solution, we will be able to determine the
exact values of squares (1, 2) and (3, 2), that is, which square receives a 1 and
which receives a 7.
2
5
6
8
3
3
6
7
8
6
4
9
3
8
6
1
4
6
5
7
2
4
5
1
9
8
9
1
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
Analyzing boxes 1, 2, and 3; placing the digits 3 and 5.
FIGURE 1.18
2
5
6
8
3
9
3
4
6
7
1,7
8
1,7
6
4
9
3
8
6
1
4
6
5
7
2
4
5
1
9
8
9
1
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
Focusing on box 1.
FIGURE 1.19
Using this strategy of analyzing the contents of three consecutive boxes, we
deduce the following placement of digits: 1 must go in (2, 5), 6 must go in (6, 7),
6 must go in (8, 6), 7 must go in (8, 3), 3 must go in (8, 5), 8 must go in (9, 6), and
5 must go in (7, 4). At this point, box 8 is complete as shown in Figure 1.20.
(Remember, each box must contain each of the digits 1 through 9.)
Once again, we use the three consecutive box strategy and deduce the following
placement of digits: 5 must go in (8, 7), 5 must go in (9, 1), 8 must go in (7, 1), 2 must
go in (8, 1), and 1 must go in (7, 3). At this point, box 7 is complete as shown in
Figure 1.21.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 13
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
4
Property
4
Property
of
of
of
of
3
of
3
1,7
of
1,7
8
of
8
Cengage
square (3, 1), as row 1 and column 2 already have a
Cengage
square (3, 1), as row 1 and column 2 already have a
can be placed only in square (1, 1) because column 2 already has a 9.
Cengage
can be placed only in square (1, 1) because column 2 already has a 9.
1
Cengage
1
or
Cengage
or
7
Cengage
7
can be placed in square (1, 2) or (3, 2) as shown
Cengage
can be placed in square (1, 2) or (3, 2) as shown
in Figure 1.19. At some point later in the solution, we will be able to determine the
Cengage
in Figure 1.19. At some point later in the solution, we will be able to determine the
exact values of squares (1, 2) and (3, 2), that is, which square receives a 1 and
Cengage
exact values of squares (1, 2) and (3, 2), that is, which square receives a 1 and
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
2
Cengage
2
1,7
Cengage
1,7
Learning
Because we have placed two new digits in box 1, we might wish to focus on
Learning
Because we have placed two new digits in box 1, we might wish to focus on
the remainder of (shaded) box 1. Notice that the digit
Learning
the remainder of (shaded) box 1. Notice that the digit
square (3, 1), as row 1 and column 2 already have a
Learning
square (3, 1), as row 1 and column 2 already have a
can be placed only in square (1, 1) because column 2 already has a 9.
Learning
can be placed only in square (1, 1) because column 2 already has a 9.
Learning
Learning
Learning
6
Learning
6
Analyzing boxes 1, 2, and 3; placing the digits 3 and 5.
Learning
Analyzing boxes 1, 2, and 3; placing the digits 3 and 5.
We now focus on box 4 and deduce the following placement of digits: 1 must
go in (4, 1), 9 must go in (5, 3), 4 must go in (4, 3), 5 must go in (6, 2), 3 must go
in (4, 2), and 2 must go in (5, 2). At this point, box 4 is complete. In addition, we
deduce that 1 must go in (9, 8), and 3 must go in (5, 6) as shown in Figure 1.22.
14 CHAPTER 1 Logic
2
5
6
8
7
3
9
3
4
6
7
1,7
8
1,7
6
4
9
3
8
6
5
1
4
6
1
5
7
3
2
4
5
1
9
6
8
8
9
1
6
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
Box 8 is complete.
FIGURE 1.20
2
5
6
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
6
7
8
2
5
1,7
8
1,7
6
4
9
3
8
6
5
1
4
6
1
5
7
3
2
4
5
1
9
6
8
8
9
1
6
5
7
5
6
3
9
5
8
6
Box 7 is complete.
FIGURE 1.21
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
1,7
8
1,7
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
8
6
5
1
4
6
1
5
7
3
2
4
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
9
1
6
5
7
5
6
3
9
1
5
8
6
Box 4 is complete.
FIGURE 1.22
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 14
Property
We now focus on box 4 and deduce the following placement of digits:
Property
We now focus on box 4 and deduce the following placement of digits:
go in (4, 1),
Property
go in (4, 1),
in (4, 2), and
Property
in (4, 2), and
deduce that
Property
deduce that
Property
Property
of
of
of
of
of
of
3
of
3
Box 7 is complete.
of
Box 7 is complete.
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
5
Cengage
5
1
Cengage
1
4
Cengage
4
7
Cengage
7
3
Cengage
3
5
Cengage
5
1
Cengage
1
9
Cengage
9
1
Cengage
1
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
5
Learning
5
6
Learning
6
3
Learning
3
Once again, we use the three consecutive box strategy and deduce the follow-
ing placement of digits: 3 must go in (6, 9), 3 must go in (7, 7), 9 must go in (2, 4),
and 9 must go in (6, 5). Now, to finish row 6, we place 4 in (6, 8) and 2 in (6, 4) as
shown in Figure 1.23. (Remember, each row must contain each of the digits 1
through 9.)
1.1 Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning 15
After we place 7 in (5, 4), column 4 is complete. (Remember, each column
must contain each of the digits 1 through 9.) This leads to placing 4 in (5, 5) and 8
in (4, 5), thus completing box 5; row 5 is finalized by placing 8 in (5, 8) as shown
in Figure 1.24.
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
1,7
8
1,7
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
9
8
6
2
5
1
4
6
1
5
9
7
3
2
4
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
9
1
6
3
5
7
5
6
3
4
9
1
5
3
8
6
Row 6 is complete.
FIGURE 1.23
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
1,7
8
1,7
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
9
8
6
7
2
5
1
4
6
1
5
8
4
9
7
3
2
4
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
9
1
6
3
5
7
5
6
3
8
4
9
1
5
3
8
6
Column 4, box 5, and row 5 are complete.
FIGURE 1.24
Now column 7 is completed by placing 4 in (2, 7) and 2 in (3, 7); placing 2 in
(2, 6) and 7 in (3, 6) completes column 6 as shown in Figure 1.25.
At this point, we deduce that the digit in (3, 2) must be 1 because row 3 can-
not have two 7’s. This in turn reveals that 7 must go in (1, 2), and box 1 is now
complete. To complete row 7, we place 4 in (7, 9) and 2 in (7, 8); row 4 is finished
with 2 in (4, 9) and 7 in (4, 8). See Figure 1.26.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 15
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
9
Property
9
3
Property
3
Property
of
of
of
of
Cengage
After we place
Cengage
After we place
7
Cengage
7
in (5, 4), column 4 is complete. (Remember, each column
Cengage
in (5, 4), column 4 is complete. (Remember, each column
must contain each of the digits 1 through 9.) This leads to placing
Cengage
must contain each of the digits 1 through 9.) This leads to placing
in (4, 5), thus completing box 5; row 5 is finalized by placing
Cengage
in (4, 5), thus completing box 5; row 5 is finalized by placing
in Figure 1.24.
Cengage
in Figure 1.24.
Cengage
Cengage
Row 6 is complete.
Cengage
Row 6 is complete.
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
8
Learning
8
3
Learning
3
5
Learning
5
7
Learning
7
4
Learning
4
5
Learning
5
3
Learning
3
As a final check, we scrutinize each box, row, and column to verify that no
box, row, or column contains the same digit twice. Congratulations, the puzzle has
been solved!
To finish rows 1, 2, and 3, 1 must go in (1, 9), 7 must go in (2, 9), and 9 must
go in (3, 9). The puzzle is now complete as shown in Figure 1.27.
16 CHAPTER 1 Logic
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
7
8
1
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
9
8
6
7
2
5
1
4
6
1
5
8
4
9
7
3
2
4
2
7
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
4
2
9
1
6
3
5
7
5
6
3
7
8
4
2
9
1
2
5
3
4
8
6
Box 1, row 7, and row 4 are complete.
FIGURE 1.26
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
1,7
8
1,7
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
9
8
6
7
2
5
1
4
6
1
5
8
4
9
7
3
2
4
2
7
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
4
2
9
1
6
3
5
7
5
6
3
8
4
9
1
5
3
8
6
Columns 7 and 6 are complete.
FIGURE 1.25
2
5
6
4
9
8
1
7
3
9
3
4
1
6
7
8
2
5
7
8
1
3
2
5
6
4
9
3
9
8
6
7
2
5
1
4
6
1
5
8
4
9
7
3
2
4
2
7
5
3
1
9
6
8
8
4
2
9
1
6
3
5
7
5
6
3
7
8
4
2
9
1
1
7
9
2
5
3
4
8
6
A completed sudoku puzzle.
FIGURE 1.27
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 16
Property
To finish rows 1, 2, and 3,
Property
To finish rows 1, 2, and 3,
go in (3, 9). The puzzle is now complete as shown in Figure 1.27.
Property
go in (3, 9). The puzzle is now complete as shown in Figure 1.27.
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
9
Property
9
Property
of
of
Box 1, row 7, and row 4 are complete.
of
Box 1, row 7, and row 4 are complete.
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
1
Cengage
1
4
Cengage
4
9
Cengage
9
7
Cengage
7
3
Cengage
3
3
Cengage
3
1
Cengage
1
9
Cengage
9
9
Cengage
9
1
Cengage
1
Box 1, row 7, and row 4 are complete.
Cengage
Box 1, row 7, and row 4 are complete.
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
2
Learning
2
5
Learning
5
6
Learning
6
3
Learning
3
17
1.1 Exercises
In Exercises 1–20, construct a Venn diagram to determine the
validity of the given argument.
1. a. 1. All master photographers are artists.
2. Ansel Adams is a master photographer.
Therefore, Ansel Adams is an artist.
b. 1. All master photographers are artists.
2. Ansel Adams is an artist.
Therefore, Ansel Adams is a master photographer.
2. a. 1. All Olympic gold medal winners are role
models.
2. Michael Phelps is an Olympic gold medal
winner.
Therefore, Michael Phelps is a role model.
b. 1. All Olympic gold medal winners are role
models.
2. Michael Phelps is a role model.
Therefore, Michael Phelps is an Olympic gold medal
winner.
3. a. 1. All homeless people are unemployed.
2. Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
Therefore, Bill Gates is not unemployed.
b. 1. All homeless people are unemployed.
2. Bill Gates is not unemployed.
Therefore, Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
4. a. 1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
2. Ralph Nader is not an actor.
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not a professional
wrestler.
b. 1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
2. Ralph Nader is not a professional wrestler.
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not an actor.
5. 1. All pesticides are harmful to the environment.
2. No fertilizer is a pesticide.
Therefore, no fertilizer is harmful to the environment.
6. 1. No one who can afford health insurance is
unemployed.
2. All politicians can afford health insurance.
Therefore, no politician is unemployed.
7. 1. No vegetarian owns a gun.
2. All policemen own guns.
Therefore, no policeman is a vegetarian.
8. 1. No professor is a millionaire.
2. No millionaire is illiterate.
Therefore, no professor is illiterate.
9. 1. All poets are loners.
2. All loners are taxi drivers.
Therefore, all poets are taxi drivers.
10. 1. All forest rangers are environmentalists.
2. All forest rangers are storytellers.
Therefore, all environmentalists are storytellers.
11. 1. Real men don’t eat quiche.
2. Clint Eastwood is a real man.
Therefore, Clint Eastwood doesn’t eat quiche.
12. 1. Real men don’t eat quiche.
2. Oscar Meyer eats quiche.
Therefore, Oscar Meyer isn’t a real man.
13. 1. All roads lead to Rome.
2. Route 66 is a road.
Therefore, Route 66 leads to Rome.
14. 1. All smiling cats talk.
2. The Cheshire Cat smiles.
Therefore, the Cheshire Cat talks.
15. 1. Some animals are dangerous.
2. A tiger is an animal.
Therefore, a tiger is dangerous.
16. 1. Some professors wear glasses.
2. Mr. Einstein wears glasses.
Therefore, Mr. Einstein is a professor.
17. 1. Some women are police officers.
2. Some police officers ride motorcycles.
Therefore, some women ride motorcycles.
18. 1. All poets are eloquent.
2. Some poets are wine connoisseurs.
Therefore, some wine connoisseurs are eloquent.
19. 1. All squares are rectangles.
2. Some quadrilaterals are squares.
Therefore, some quadrilaterals are rectangles.
20. 1. All squares are rectangles.
2. Some quadrilaterals are rectangles.
Therefore, some quadrilaterals are squares.
21. Classify each argument as deductive or inductive.
a. 1. My television set did not work two nights ago.
2. My television set did not work last night.
Therefore, my television set is broken.
b. 1. All electronic devices give their owners grief.
2. My television set is an electronic device.
Therefore, my television set gives me grief.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 17
Property
Property
2. Ralph Nader is not an actor.
Property
2. Ralph Nader is not an actor.
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not a professional
Property
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not a professional
1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
Property
1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
Property
2. Ralph Nader is not a professional wrestler.
Property
2. Ralph Nader is not a professional wrestler.
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not an actor.
Property
Therefore, Ralph Nader is not an actor.
1. All pesticides are harmful to the environment.
Property
1. All pesticides are harmful to the environment.
Property
2. No fertilizer is a pesticide.
Property
2. No fertilizer is a pesticide.
of
Therefore, Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
of
Therefore, Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
of
1. All professional wrestlers are actors.
of
Cengage
Cengage
Therefore, Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
Cengage
Therefore, Bill Gates is not a homeless person.
1. All smiling cats talk.
Cengage
1. All smiling cats talk.
Cengage
2. The Cheshire Cat smiles.
Cengage
2. The Cheshire Cat smiles.
Therefore, the Cheshire Cat talks.
Cengage
Therefore, the Cheshire Cat talks.
15.
Cengage
15.
Learning
Therefore, Clint Eastwood doesn’t eat quiche.
Learning
Therefore, Clint Eastwood doesn’t eat quiche.
1. Real men don’t eat quiche.
Learning
1. Real men don’t eat quiche.
Learning
2. Oscar Meyer eats quiche.
Learning
2. Oscar Meyer eats quiche.
Therefore, Oscar Meyer isn’t a real man.
Learning
Therefore, Oscar Meyer isn’t a real man.
1. All roads lead to Rome.
Learning
1. All roads lead to Rome.
Learning
2. Route 66 is a road.
Learning
2. Route 66 is a road.
Therefore, Route 66 leads to Rome.
Learning
Therefore, Route 66 leads to Rome.
1. All smiling cats talk.
Learning
1. All smiling cats talk.
18 CHAPTER 1 Logic
22. Classify each argument as deductive or inductive.
a. 1. I ate a chili dog at Joe’s and got indigestion.
2. I ate a chili dog at Ruby’s and got indigestion.
Therefore, chili dogs give me indigestion.
b. 1. All spicy foods give me indigestion.
2. Chili dogs are spicy food.
Therefore, chili dogs give me indigestion.
In Exercises 23–32, fill in the blank with what is most likely to be
the next number. Explain (using complete sentences) the pattern
generated by your answer.
23. 3, 8, 13, 18, _____
24. 10, 11, 13, 16, _____
25. 0, 2, 6, 12, _____
26. 1, 2, 5, 10, _____
27. 1, 4, 9, 16, _____
28. 1, 8, 27, 64, _____
29. 2, 3, 5, 7, 11, _____
30. 1, 1, 2, 3, 5, _____
31. 5, 8, 11, 2, _____
32. 12, 5, 10, 3, _____
In Exercises 33–36, fill in the blanks with what are most likely to
be the next letters. Explain (using complete sentences) the pattern
generated by your answers.
33. O, T, T, F, _____, _____
34. T, F, S, E, _____, _____
35. F, S, S, M, _____, _____
36. J, F, M, A, _____, _____
In Exercises 37–42, explain the general rule or pattern used to
assign the given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
letter that fits the pattern.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
43. Find two different numbers that could be used to fill in
the blank.
1, 4, 7, 10, _____
Explain the pattern generated by each of your answers.
44. Find five different numbers that could be used to fill in
the blank.
7, 14, 21, 28, ______
Explain the pattern generated by each of your
answers.
45. Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
is a solution of the equation ax
2
bx c 0.
HINT: Substitute the fraction for x in ax
2
bx c and
simplify.
46. Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
is a solution of the equation ax
2
bx c 0.
HINT: Substitute the fraction for x in ax
2
bx c and
simplify.
47. As a review of algebra, use the Quadratic Formula to
solve
x
2
6x 7 0
48. As a review of algebra, use the Quadratic Formula to
solve
x
2
2x 4 0
Solve the sudoku puzzles in Exercises 49–54.
49.
7
295
5
3
61
63
4
89
14
3
2156
6
1
9
43
2
8
5
x
b 2b
2
4ac
2a
x
b 2b
2
4ac
2a
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
c s t o _____
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
i u a o _____
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
j v b p _____
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
c r p g _____
banana strawberry asparagus eggplant orange
bz t u _____
banana strawberry asparagus eggplant orange
yr g p _____
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 18
Property
In Exercises 37–42, explain the general rule or pattern used to
Property
In Exercises 37–42, explain the general rule or pattern used to
assign the given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
Property
assign the given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
Property
Property
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
c s t o _____
Property
c s t o _____
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
Property
Property
c s t o _____
Property
c s t o _____
Property
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
Property
circle square trapezoid octagon rectangle
Property
Property
of
Cengage
is a solution of the equation
Cengage
is a solution of the equation
HINT:
Cengage
HINT:
Substitute the fraction for
Cengage
Substitute the fraction for
simplify.
Cengage
simplify.
Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
Cengage
Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
Learning
Explain the pattern generated by each of your
Learning
Explain the pattern generated by each of your
Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
Learning
Example 1 utilized the Quadratic Formula. Verify that
is a solution of the equation
Learning
is a solution of the equation
Substitute the fraction for
Learning
Substitute the fraction for
2
Learning
2
b
Learning
b
2b2
Learning
2b2
2
Learning
2
Learning
4
Learning
4
ac
Learning
ac
Learning
2
Learning
2
Learning
2
Learning
2
a
Learning
a
50.
51.
52.
53.
2
4
1
7
5
3
6
7
9
8
5
7
6
8
3
1
6
7
7
3
1
5
2
6
9
8
9
6
2
3
6
7
6
7
2
3
8
5
8
6
3
7
2
1
6
4
9
5
1
2
4
5
5
8
4
5
7
6
3
7
9
5
2
5
7
8
9
3
3
9
8
5
6
7
2
9
6
2
4
6
8
1
6
2
7
9
3
7
9
2
4
2
3
2
7
8
6
5
9
4
6
4
1
4
6
5
5
6
2
3
7
9
4
2
3
9
1.1 Exercises 19
54.
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
55. Explain the difference between deductive reasoning
and inductive reasoning.
56. Explain the difference between truth and validity.
57. What is a syllogism? Give an example of a syllogism
that relates to your life.
History Questions
58. From the days of the ancient Greeks, the study of
logic has been mandatory in what two professions?
Why?
59. Who developed a formal system of deductive logic
based on arguments?
60. What was the name of the school Aristotle founded?
What does it mean?
61. How did Aristotle’s school of thought differ from
Plato’s?
Web Project
62. Obtain a sudoku puzzle and its solution from a popular
web site. Some useful links for this web project are
listed on the text web site:
www.cengage.com/math/johnson
2
4
3
7
4
1
6
1
8
3
5
2
7
8
9
3
4
12
4
8
8
1
2
6
8
5
9
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 19
Property
Property
Property
5
Property
5
Property
Property
Property
1
Property
1
9
Property
9
5
Property
5
4
Property
4
of
of
of
of
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
4
Cengage
4
Explain the difference between deductive reasoning
Cengage
Explain the difference between deductive reasoning
and inductive reasoning.
Cengage
and inductive reasoning.
56.
Cengage
56.
Explain the difference between truth and validity.
Cengage
Explain the difference between truth and validity.
57.
Cengage
57.
What is a syllogism? Give an example of a syllogism
Cengage
What is a syllogism? Give an example of a syllogism
Learning
Answer the following questions using complete
Learning
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Learning
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
Learning
Concept Questions
Explain the difference between deductive reasoning
Learning
Explain the difference between deductive reasoning
and inductive reasoning.
Learning
and inductive reasoning.
Learning
Learning
Learning
1.2 Symbolic Logic
Objectives
Identify simple statements
Express a compound statement in symbolic form
Create the negation of a statement
Express a conditional statement in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions
The syllogism ruled the study of logic for nearly 2,000 years and was not sup-
planted until the development of symbolic logic in the late seventeenth century. As
its name implies, symbolic logic involves the use of symbols and algebraic manip-
ulations in logic.
Statements
All logical reasoning is based on statements. A statement is a sentence that is
either true or false.
EXAMPLE 1 IDENTIFYING STATEMENTS Which of the following are statements? Why
or why not?
a. Apple manufactures computers.
b. Apple manufactures the world’s best computers.
c. Did you buy a Dell?
d. A $2,000 computer that is discounted 25% will cost $1,000.
e. I am telling a lie.
SOLUTION a. The sentence “Apple manufactures computers” is true; therefore, it is a statement.
b. The sentence “Apple manufactures the world’s best computers” is an opinion, and as
such, it is neither true nor false. It is true for some people and false for others. Therefore,
it is not a statement.
c. The sentence “Did you buy a Dell?” is a question. As such, it is neither true nor false; it
is not a statement.
d. The sentence “A $2,000 computer that is discounted 25% will cost $1,000” is false; there-
fore, it is a statement. (A $2,000 computer that is discounted 25% would cost $1,500.)
e. The sentence “I am telling a lie” is a self-contradiction, or paradox. If it were true, the
speaker would be telling a lie, but in telling the truth, the speaker would be contradicting
the statement that he or she was lying; if it were false, the speaker would not be telling a
lie, but in not telling a lie, the speaker would be contradicting the statement that he or she
was lying. The sentence is not a statement.
By tradition, symbolic logic uses lowercase letters as labels for statements.
The most frequently used letters are p, q, r, s, and t. We can label the statement “It
is snowing” as statement p in the following manner:
p: It is snowing.
If it is snowing, p is labeled true, whereas if it is not snowing, p is labeled false.
20
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 20
Property
Did you buy a Dell?
Property
Did you buy a Dell?
A $2,000 computer that is discounted 25% will cost $1,000.
Property
A $2,000 computer that is discounted 25% will cost $1,000.
I am telling a lie.
Property
I am telling a lie.
a.
Property
a.
The sentence “Apple manufactures computers” is true; therefore, it is a statement.
Property
The sentence “Apple manufactures computers” is true; therefore, it is a statement.
b.
Property
b.
The sentence “Apple manufactures the world’s best computers” is an opinion, and as
Property
The sentence “Apple manufactures the world’s best computers” is an opinion, and as
such, it is neither true nor false. It is true for some people and false for others. Therefore,
Property
such, it is neither true nor false. It is true for some people and false for others. Therefore,
Property
of
Apple manufactures computers.
of
Apple manufactures computers.
Apple manufactures the world’s best computers.
of
Apple manufactures the world’s best computers.
Did you buy a Dell?
of
Did you buy a Dell?
Cengage
All logical reasoning is based on statements. A
Cengage
All logical reasoning is based on statements. A
IDENTIFYING STATEMENTS
Cengage
IDENTIFYING STATEMENTS
Apple manufactures computers.
Cengage
Apple manufactures computers.
Learning
Express a conditional statement in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions
Learning
Express a conditional statement in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions
The syllogism ruled the study of logic for nearly 2,000 years and was not sup-
Learning
The syllogism ruled the study of logic for nearly 2,000 years and was not sup-
planted until the development of symbolic logic in the late seventeenth century. As
Learning
planted until the development of symbolic logic in the late seventeenth century. As
its name implies, symbolic logic involves the use of symbols and algebraic manip-
Learning
its name implies, symbolic logic involves the use of symbols and algebraic manip-
Compound Statements and Logical Connectives
It is easy to determine whether a statement such as “Charles donated blood” is true
or false; either he did or he didn’t. However, not all statements are so simple; some
are more involved. For example, the truth of “Charles donated blood and did not
wash his car, or he went to the library,” depends on the truth of the individual
pieces that make up the larger, compound statement. A compound statement is a
statement that contains one or more simpler statements. Acompound statement can
be formed by inserting the word not into a simpler statement or by joining two or
more statements with connective words such as and, or, if ... then ... , only if, and
if and only if. The compound statement “Charles did not wash his car” is formed
from the simpler statement “Charles did wash his car.” The compound statement
“Charles donated blood and did not wash his car, or he went to the library” consists
of three statements, each of which may be true or false.
Figure 1.28 diagrams two equivalent compound statements.
1.2 Symbolic Logic 21
out
in A
in B
in A
in B
Or Not
out
“neither A nor B “not A and not Bmeans
Not
Not
And
Technicians and engineers use compound statements and logical
connectives to study the flow of electricity through switching circuits.
FIGURE 1.28
When is a compound statement true? Before we can answer this question, we
must first examine the various ways in which statements can be connected. Depend-
ing on how the statements are connected, the resulting compound statement can be
a negation, a conjunction, a disjunction, a conditional, or any combination thereof.
The Negation p
The negation of a statement is the denial of the statement and is represented by the
symbol . The negation is frequently formed by inserting the word not. For exam-
ple, given the statement “p: It is snowing,” the negation would be “p: It is not
snowing.” If it is snowing, p is true and p is false. Similarly, if it is not snowing,
p is false and p is true. A statement and its negation always have opposite truth
values; when one is true, the other is false. Because the truth of the negation de-
pends on the truth of the original statement, a negation is classified as a compound
statement.
EXAMPLE 2 WRITING A NEGATION Write a sentence that represents the negation of each
statement:
a. The senator is a Democrat. b. The senator is not a Democrat.
c. Some senators are Republicans. d. All senators are Republicans.
e. No senator is a Republican.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 21
Property
must first examine the various ways in which statements can be connected. Depend-
Property
must first examine the various ways in which statements can be connected. Depend-
ing on how the statements are connected, the resulting compound statement can be
Property
ing on how the statements are connected, the resulting compound statement can be
a
Property
a
negation,
Property
negation,
of
When is a compound statement true? Before we can answer this question, we
of
When is a compound statement true? Before we can answer this question, we
must first examine the various ways in which statements can be connected. Depend-
of
must first examine the various ways in which statements can be connected. Depend-
ing on how the statements are connected, the resulting compound statement can be
of
ing on how the statements are connected, the resulting compound statement can be
Cengage
A
Cengage
A
nor
Cengage
nor
B
Cengage
B
“not
Cengage
“not
Cengage
Cengage
Technicians and engineers use compound statements and logical
Cengage
Technicians and engineers use compound statements and logical
connectives to study the flow of electricity through switching circuits.
Cengage
connectives to study the flow of electricity through switching circuits.
When is a compound statement true? Before we can answer this question, we
Cengage
When is a compound statement true? Before we can answer this question, we
Learning
pler statement “Charles did wash his car.” The compound statement
Learning
pler statement “Charles did wash his car.” The compound statement
he went to the library” consists
Learning
he went to the library” consists
of three statements, each of which may be true or false.
Learning
of three statements, each of which may be true or false.
Figure 1.28 diagrams two equivalent compound statements.
Learning
Figure 1.28 diagrams two equivalent compound statements.
in
Learning
in
A
Learning
A
Learning
Learning
Learning
out
Learning
out
Not
Learning
Not
SOLUTION a. The negation of “The senator is a Democrat” is “The senator is not a Democrat.”
b. The negation of “The senator is not a Democrat” is “The senator is a Democrat.”
c. A common error would be to say that the negation of “Some senators are Republicans”
is “Some senators are not Republicans.” However, “Some senators are Republicans” is
not denied by “Some senators are not Republicans.” The statement “Some senators are
Republicans” implies that at least one senator is a Republican. The negation of this state-
ment is “It is not the case that at least one senator is a Republican,” or (more commonly
phrased) the negation is “No senator is a Republican.”
d. The negation of “All senators are Republicans” is “It is not the case that all senators are
Republicans,” or “There exists a senator who is not a Republican,” or (more commonly
phrased) “Some senators are not Republicans.”
e. The negation of “No senator is a Republican” is “It is not the case that no senator is a
Republican” or, in other words, “There exists at least one senator who is a Republican.”
If “some” is interpreted as meaning “at least one,” the negation can be expressed as
“Some senators are Republicans.”
The words some, all, and no (or none) are referred to as quantifiers. Parts (c)
through (e) of Example 2 contain quantifiers. The linked pairs of quantified state-
ments shown in Figure 1.29 are negations of each other.
22 CHAPTER 1 Logic
All p are q.
Some p are q.
No p are q.
Some p are not q.
Negations of statements containing quantifiers.FIGURE 1.29
The Conjunction p q
Consider the statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.”
This is a compound statement, because it consists of two statements—“Norma Rae
is a union member” and “she (Norma Rae) is a Democrat”—and the connective
word and. Such a compound statement is referred to as a conjunction. A conjunc-
tion consists of two or more statements connected by the word and. We use the
symbol to represent the word and; thus, the conjunction “p q” represents the
compound statement “p and q.
EXAMPLE 3 TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS Using the symbolic represen-
tations
p: Norma Rae is a union member.
q: Norma Rae is a Democrat.
express the following compound statements in symbolic form:
a. Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.
b. Norma Rae is a union member and she is not a Democrat.
SOLUTION a. The compound statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat” can be
represented as p q.
b. The compound statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is not a Democrat”
can be represented as p q.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 22
Property
Property
Consider the statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.”
Property
Consider the statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.”
This is a compound statement, because it consists of two statements—“Norma Rae
Property
This is a compound statement, because it consists of two statements—“Norma Rae
is a union member” and “she (Norma Rae) is a Democrat”—and the connective
Property
is a union member” and “she (Norma Rae) is a Democrat”—and the connective
word
Property
word
and.
Property
and.
tion
Property
tion
consists of two or more statements connected by the word
Property
consists of two or more statements connected by the word
symbol
Property
symbol
compound statement “
Property
compound statement “
3
Property
3
of
The Conjunction
of
The Conjunction
Consider the statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.”
of
Consider the statement “Norma Rae is a union member and she is a Democrat.”
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
.
Cengage
.
Some
Cengage
Some
p
Cengage
p
are not
Cengage
are not
q
Cengage
q
Negations of statements containing quantifiers.
Cengage
Negations of statements containing quantifiers.
The Conjunction
Cengage
The Conjunction
Learning
Republican” or, in other words, “There exists at least one senator who
Learning
Republican” or, in other words, “There exists at least one senator who
is
Learning
is
If “some” is interpreted as meaning “at least one,” the negation can be expressed as
Learning
If “some” is interpreted as meaning “at least one,” the negation can be expressed as
) are referred to as
Learning
) are referred to as
quantifiers.
Learning
quantifiers.
through (e) of Example 2 contain quantifiers. The linked pairs of quantified state-
Learning
through (e) of Example 2 contain quantifiers. The linked pairs of quantified state-
ments shown in Figure 1.29 are negations of each other.
Learning
ments shown in Figure 1.29 are negations of each other.
Learning
Learning
The Disjunction p q
When statements are connected by the word or, a disjunction is formed. We use
the symbol to represent the word or. Thus, the disjunction “p q” represents the
compound statement “p or q.” We can interpret the word or in two ways. Consider
the statements
p: Kaitlin is a registered Republican.
q: Paki is a registered Republican.
The statement “Kaitlin is a registered Republican or Paki is a registered Republi-
can” can be symbolized as p q. Notice that it is possible that both Kaitlin and
Paki are registered Republicans. In this example, or includes the possibility that
both things may happen. In this case, we are working with the inclusive or.
Now consider the statements
p: Kaitlin is a registered Republican.
q: Kaitlin is a registered Democrat.
The statement “Kaitlin is a registered Republican or Kaitlin is a registered Demo-
crat” does not include the possibility that both may happen; one statement excludes
the other. When this happens, we are working with the exclusive or. In our study
of symbolic logic (as in most mathematics), we will always use the inclusive or.
Therefore, “p or q” means “p or q or both.”
EXAMPLE 4 TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS Using the symbolic represen-
tations
p: Juanita is a college graduate.
q: Juanita is employed.
express the following compound statements in words:
a. p q b. p q
c. p q d. p q
SOLUTION a. p q represents the statement “Juanita is a college graduate or Juanita is employed (or
both).”
b. p q represents the statement “Juanita is a college graduate and Juanita is employed.”
c. p q represents the statement “Juanita is a college graduate or Juanita is not
employed.”
d. p q represents the statement “Juanita is not a college graduate and Juanita is
employed.”
The Conditional p q
Consider the statement “If it is raining, then the streets are wet.” This is a com-
pound statement because it connects two statements, namely, “it is raining” and
“the streets are wet.” Notice that the statements are connected with “if . . . then . . .”
phrasing. Any statement of the form “if p then q” is called a conditional (or an
implication); p is called the hypothesis (or premise) of the conditional, and q is
called the conclusion of the conditional. The conditional “if p then q” is repre-
sented by the symbols “p q” (p implies q). When people use conditionals in
1.2 Symbolic Logic 23
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:33 AM Page 23
Property
a.
Property
a.
p
Property
p
c.
Property
c.
p
Property
p
Property
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
a.
Property
a.
p
Property
p
Property
of
q:
of
q:
Juanita is employed.
of
Juanita is employed.
express the following compound statements in words:
of
express the following compound statements in words:
of
q
of
q
Cengage
include the possibility that both may happen; one statement
Cengage
include the possibility that both may happen; one statement
the other. When this happens, we are working with the
Cengage
the other. When this happens, we are working with the
of symbolic logic (as in most mathematics), we will always use the
Cengage
of symbolic logic (as in most mathematics), we will always use the
” means “
Cengage
” means “
p
Cengage
p
” means “p” means “
Cengage
” means “p” means “
or
Cengage
or
q
Cengage
q
or both.”
Cengage
or both.”
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
Cengage
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
Juanita is a college graduate.
Cengage
Juanita is a college graduate.
Juanita is employed.
Cengage
Juanita is employed.
express the following compound statements in words:
Cengage
express the following compound statements in words:
Learning
Notice that it is possible that
Learning
Notice that it is possible that
includes the possibility that
Learning
includes the possibility that
both things may happen. In this case, we are working with the
Learning
both things may happen. In this case, we are working with the
Kaitlin is a registered Democrat.
Learning
Kaitlin is a registered Democrat.
The statement “Kaitlin is a registered Republican or Kaitlin is a registered Demo-
Learning
The statement “Kaitlin is a registered Republican or Kaitlin is a registered Demo-
include the possibility that both may happen; one statement
Learning
include the possibility that both may happen; one statement
the other. When this happens, we are working with the
Learning
the other. When this happens, we are working with the
24 CHAPTER 1 Logic
GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ 1646–1716
Leibniz’s affinity
for logic was char-
acterized by his
search for a charac-
teristica universalis,
or “universal charac-
ter.” Leibniz be-
lieved that by com-
bining logic and
mathematics, a gen-
eral symbolic lan-
guage could be created in which all
scientific problems could be solved with
a minimum of effort. In this universal
language, statements and the logical
relationships between them would be
represented by letters and symbols. In
In the early 1670s, Leibniz invented one of the world’s first mechanical
calculating machines. Leibniz’s machine could multiply and divide, whereas
an earlier machine invented by Blaise Pascal (see Chapter 3) could only add
and subtract.
© Science Museum/SSPL/The Image Works
Leibniz’s words, “All truths of reason
would be reduced to a kind of calculus,
and the errors would only be errors of
computation.” In essence, Leibniz be-
lieved that once a problem had been
translated into this universal language of
symbolic logic, it would be solved auto-
matically by simply applying the mathe-
matical rules that governed the manipu-
lation of the symbols.
Leibniz’s work in the field of symbolic
logic did not arouse much academic cu-
riosity; many say that it was too far
ahead of its time. The study of symbolic
logic was not systematically investigated
again until the nineteenth century.
I
n addition to cofounding
calculus (see Chapter 13),
the German-born Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz contributed
much to the development of
symbolic logic. A precocious
child, Leibniz was self-taught in
many areas. He taught himself
Latin at the age of eight and began
the study of Greek when he was twelve.
In the process, he was exposed to the
writings of Aristotle and became in-
trigued by formalized logic.
At the age of fifteen, Leibniz entered
the University of Leipzig to study law. He
received his bachelor’s degree two
years later, earned his master’s degree
the following year, and then transferred
to the University of Nuremberg.
Leibniz received his doctorate in law
within a year and was immediately
offered a professorship but refused it,
saying that he had “other things in
mind.” Besides law, these “other things”
included politics, religion, history, litera-
ture, metaphysics, philosophy, logic,
and mathematics. Thereafter, Leibniz
worked under the sponsorship of the
courts of various nobles, serving as
lawyer, historian, and librarian to the
elite. At one point, Leibniz was offered
the position of librarian at the Vatican
but declined the offer.
© North Wind/North Wind Picture Archives —
All rights reserved.
Historical
Note
everyday speech, they often omit the word then, as in “If it is raining, the streets
are wet.” Alternatively, the conditional “if p then q” may be phrased as “q if p
(“The streets are wet if it is raining”).
EXAMPLE 5 TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS Using the symbolic represen-
tations
p: I am healthy.
q: I eat junk food.
r: I exercise regularly.
express the following compound statements in symbolic form:
a. I am healthy if I exercise regularly.
b. If I eat junk food and do not exercise, then I am not healthy.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 24
Property
Property
Property
lawyer, historian, and librarian to the
Property
lawyer, historian, and librarian to the
elite. At one point, Leibniz was offered
Property
elite. At one point, Leibniz was offered
the position of librarian at the Vatican
Property
the position of librarian at the Vatican
of
of
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
matically by simply applying the mathe-
Learning
matically by simply applying the mathe-
matical rules that governed the manipu-
Learning
matical rules that governed the manipu-
lation of the symbols.
Learning
lation of the symbols.
Leibniz’s work in the field of symbolic
Learning
Leibniz’s work in the field of symbolic
logic did not arouse much academic cu-
Learning
logic did not arouse much academic cu-
riosity; many say that it was too far
Learning
riosity; many say that it was too far
ahead of its time. The study of symbolic
Learning
ahead of its time. The study of symbolic
logic was not systematically investigated
Learning
logic was not systematically investigated
again until the nineteenth century.
Learning
again until the nineteenth century.
1.2 Symbolic Logic 25
SOLUTION a. “I am healthy if I exercise regularly” is a conditional (if ... then . . . ) and can be re-
phrased as follows:
I exercise regularly, I am healthy.”
Statement r Statement p
is the premise. is the conclusion.
The given compound statement can be expressed as r p.
b. “If I eat junk food and do not exercise, then I am not healthy” is a conditional
(if ... then . . . ) that contains a conjunction (and) and two negations (not):
“If I eat junk food do exercise, then I am healthy.”
The premise contains The conclusion
a conjunction and a negation. contains a negation.
The premise of the conditional can be represented by q r, while the conclusion
can be represented by p. Thus, the given compound statement has the symbolic form
(q r) p.
EXAMPLE 6 TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS Express the following statements
in symbolic form:
a. All mammals are warm-blooded.
b. No snake is warm-blooded.
SOLUTION a. The statement “All mammals are warm-blooded” can be rephrased as “If it is a mam-
mal, then it is warm-blooded.” Therefore, we define two simple statements p and q as
p: It is a mammal.
q: It is warm-blooded.
The statement now has the form
it is a mammal, it is warm-blooded.”
Statement p Statement q
is the premise. is the conclusion.
and can be expressed as p q. In general, any statement of the form “All p are q” can
be symbolized as p q.
b. The statement “No snake is warm-blooded” can be rephrased as “If it is a snake, then it
is not warm-blooded.” Therefore, we define two simple statements p and q as
p: It is a snake.
q: It is warm-blooded.
The statement now has the form
it is a snake, it is warm-blooded.”
Statement p The negation of statement q
is the premise. is the conclusion.
and can be expressed as p q. In general, any statement of the form “No p is q” can
be symbolized as p q.
↑↑↑↑
notthenIf
↑↑↑↑
thenIf
↑↑↑↑
notnotand
↑↑↑↑
thenIf
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 25
Property
Property
of
p:
of
p:
q:
of
q:
It is warm-blooded.
of
It is warm-blooded.
The statement now has the form
of
The statement now has the form
Cengage
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
Cengage
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
All mammals are warm-blooded.
Cengage
All mammals are warm-blooded.
No snake is warm-blooded.
Cengage
No snake is warm-blooded.
The statement “All mammals are warm-blooded” can be rephrased as “If it is a mam-
Cengage
The statement “All mammals are warm-blooded” can be rephrased as “If it is a mam-
mal, then it is warm-blooded.” Therefore, we define two simple statements
Cengage
mal, then it is warm-blooded.” Therefore, we define two simple statements
It is a mammal.
Cengage
It is a mammal.
It is warm-blooded.
Cengage
It is warm-blooded.
Learning
The premise contains The conclusion
Learning
The premise contains The conclusion
a conjunction and a negation. contains a negation.
Learning
a conjunction and a negation. contains a negation.
The premise of the conditional can be represented by
Learning
The premise of the conditional can be represented by
q
Learning
q
Learning
Learning
Thus, the given compound statement has the symbolic form
Learning
Thus, the given compound statement has the symbolic form
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
Learning
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
Learning
↑↑
Learning
↑↑
26 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
As Example 6 shows, conditionals are not always expressed in the form “if p then
q.” In addition to “all p are q,” other standard forms of a conditional include state-
ments that contain the word sufficient or necessary.
Consider the statement “Being a mammal is sufficient for being warm-
blooded.” One definition of the word sufficient is “adequate.” Therefore, “being a
mammal” is an adequate condition for “being warm-blooded”; hence, “being a mam-
mal” implies “being warm-blooded.” Logically, the statement “Being a mammal is
sufficient for being warm-blooded” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “p is sufficient for q” is an
alternative form of the conditional “if p then q” and can be symbolized as p
q.
“Being a mammal” is a sufficient (adequate) condition for “being warm-
blooded,” but is it a necessary condition? Of course not: some animals are warm-
blooded but are not mammals (chickens, for example). One definition of the word
necessary is “required.” Therefore, “being a mammal” is not required for “being
warm-blooded.” However, is “being warm-blooded” a necessary (required) condi-
tion for “being a mammal”? Of course it is: all mammals are warm-blooded (that is,
there are no cold-blooded mammals). Logically, the statement “being warm-blooded
is necessary for being a mammal” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “q is necessary for p” is an
alternative form of the conditional “if p then q” and can be symbolized as p
q.
In summary, a sufficient condition is the hypothesis or premise of a condi-
tional statement, whereas a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional
statement.
p: hypothesis p implies qq: conclusion
EXAMPLE 7 TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS Using the symbolic represen-
tations
p: A person obeys the law.
q: A person is arrested.
express the following compound statements in symbolic form:
a. Being arrested is necessary for not obeying the law.
b. Obeying the law is sufficient for not being arrested.
SOLUTION a. “Being arrested” is a necessary condition; hence, “a person is arrested” is the conclusion
of a conditional statement.
A necessary condition.
Therefore, the statement “Being arrested is necessary for not obeying the law” can be
rephrased as follows:
a person does obey the law, the person is arrested.”
The negation of statement p Statement q is the
is the premise. conclusion.
The given compound statement can be expressed as p q.
↑↑
↑↑
thennotIf
A person is
arrested.
A person does
not obey the law.
Necessary conditionSufficient condition
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 26
Property
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
Property
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
tations
Property
tations
p:
Property
p:
A person obeys the law.
Property
A person obeys the law.
q:
Property
q:
A person is arrested.
Property
A person is arrested.
express the following compound statements in symbolic form:
Property
express the following compound statements in symbolic form:
a.
Property
a.
Being arrested is necessary for not obeying the law.
Property
Being arrested is necessary for not obeying the law.
b.
Property
b.
Property
of
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
of
TRANSLATING WORDS INTO SYMBOLS
Cengage
is necessary for being a mammal” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
Cengage
is necessary for being a mammal” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “
Cengage
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “
alternative form of the conditional “if
Cengage
alternative form of the conditional “if
p
Cengage
p
then
Cengage
then
q
Cengage
q
” and can be symbolized as
Cengage
” and can be symbolized as
In summary, a sufficient condition is the hypothesis or premise of a condi-
Cengage
In summary, a sufficient condition is the hypothesis or premise of a condi-
tional statement, whereas a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional
Cengage
tional statement, whereas a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional
hypothesis
Cengage
hypothesis
Sufficient condition
Cengage
Sufficient condition
Cengage
Learning
” and can be symbolized as
Learning
” and can be symbolized as
(adequate) condition for “being warm-
Learning
(adequate) condition for “being warm-
condition? Of course not: some animals are warm-
Learning
condition? Of course not: some animals are warm-
blooded but are not mammals (chickens, for example). One definition of the word
Learning
blooded but are not mammals (chickens, for example). One definition of the word
is “required.” Therefore, “being a mammal” is not required for “being
Learning
is “required.” Therefore, “being a mammal” is not required for “being
warm-blooded.” However, is “being warm-blooded” a necessary (required) condi-
Learning
warm-blooded.” However, is “being warm-blooded” a necessary (required) condi-
tion for “being a mammal”? Of course it is: all mammals
Learning
tion for “being a mammal”? Of course it is: all mammals
are
Learning
are
there are no cold-blooded mammals). Logically, the statement “being warm-blooded
Learning
there are no cold-blooded mammals). Logically, the statement “being warm-blooded
is necessary for being a mammal” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
Learning
is necessary for being a mammal” is equivalent to saying “If it is a mammal, then it
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “
Learning
is warm-blooded.” Consequently, the general statement “
b. “Obeying the law” is a sufficient condition; hence, “A person obeys the law” is the
premise of a conditional statement.
A sufficient condition.
Therefore, the statement “Obeying the law is sufficient for not being arrested” can be
rephrased as follows:
a person obeys the law, the person is arrested.”
Statement p The negation of statement q
is the premise. is the conclusion.
The given compound statement can be expressed as p q.
↑↑
↑↑
notthenIf
A person is not arrested.A person obeys the law.
1.2 Exercises 27
Statement Symbol Read as . . .
negation p not p
conjunction p qpand q
disjunction p qpor q
conditional p
q if p, then q
(implication) p is sufficient for q
q is necessary for p
Logical connectives.FIGURE 1.30
We have seen that a statement is a sentence that is either true or false and that
connecting two or more statements forms a compound statement. Figure 1.30 sum-
marizes the logical connectives and symbols that were introduced in this section.
The various connectives have been defined; we can now proceed in our analysis of
the conditions under which a compound statement is true. This analysis is carried
out in the next section.
1.2 Exercises
1. Which of the following are statements? Why or why
not?
a. George Washington was the first president of the
United States.
b. Abraham Lincoln was the second president of the
United States.
c. Who was the first vice president of the United
States?
d. Abraham Lincoln was the best president.
2. Which of the following are statements? Why or why
not?
a. 3 5 6
b. Solve the equation 2x 5 3.
c. x
2
1 0 has no solution.
d. x
2
1 (x 1)(x 1)
e. Is a rational number?12
3. Determine which pairs of statements are negations of
each other.
a. All of the fruits are red.
b. None of the fruits is red.
c. Some of the fruits are red.
d. Some of the fruits are not red.
4. Determine which pairs of statements are negations of
each other.
a. Some of the beverages contain caffeine.
b. Some of the beverages do not contain caffeine.
c. None of the beverages contain caffeine.
d. All of the beverages contain caffeine.
5. Write a sentence that represents the negation of each
statement.
a. Her dress is not red.
b. Some computers are priced under $100.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 27
Property
Property
Property
xercises
Property
xercises
Which of the following are statements? Why or why
Property
Which of the following are statements? Why or why
George Washington was the first president of the
Property
George Washington was the first president of the
United States.
Property
United States.
of
of
of
FIGURE 1.30
of
FIGURE 1.30
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Statement Symbol Read as . . .
Cengage
Statement Symbol Read as . . .
Cengage
not
Cengage
not
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
qp
Cengage
qp
and
Cengage
and
q
Cengage
q
Cengage
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
qp
Cengage
qp
or
Cengage
or
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
(implication)
Cengage
(implication)
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
qp
Cengage
qp
Cengage
Cengage
qp
Cengage
qp
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
Learning
q
Learning
q
.
Learning
.
Learning
Learning
We have seen that a statement is a sentence that is either true or false and that
Learning
We have seen that a statement is a sentence that is either true or false and that
connecting two or more statements forms a compound statement. Figure 1.30 sum-
Learning
connecting two or more statements forms a compound statement. Figure 1.30 sum-
marizes the logical connectives and symbols that were introduced in this section.
Learning
marizes the logical connectives and symbols that were introduced in this section.
The various connectives have been defined; we can now proceed in our analysis of
Learning
The various connectives have been defined; we can now proceed in our analysis of
the conditions under which a compound statement is true. This analysis is carried
Learning
the conditions under which a compound statement is true. This analysis is carried
f. Riding a motorcycle or playing the guitar is neces-
sary for wearing a leather jacket.
10. Using the symbolic representations
p: The car costs $70,000.
q: The car goes 140 mph.
r: The car is red.
express the following compound statements in sym-
bolic form.
a. All red cars go 140 mph.
b. The car is red, goes 140 mph, and does not cost
$70,000.
c. If the car does not cost $70,000, it does not go
140 mph.
d. The car is red and it does not go 140 mph or cost
$70,000.
e. Being able to go 140 mph is sufficient for a car to
cost $70,000 or be red.
f. Not being red is necessary for a car to cost $70,000
and not go 140 mph.
In Exercises 11–34, translate the sentence into symbolic form. Be
sure to define each letter you use. (More than one answer is
possible.)
11. All squares are rectangles.
12. All people born in the United States are American
citizens.
13. No square is a triangle.
14. No convicted felon is eligible to vote.
15. All whole numbers are even or odd.
16. All muscle cars from the Sixties are polluters.
17. No whole number is greater than 3 and less than 4.
18. No electric-powered car is a polluter.
19. Being an orthodontist is sufficient for being a dentist.
20. Being an author is sufficient for being literate.
21. Knowing Morse code is necessary for operating a
telegraph.
22. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
23. Being a monkey is sufficient for not being an ape.
24. Being a chimpanzee is sufficient for not being a
monkey.
25. Not being a monkey is necessary for being an ape.
26. Not being a chimpanzee is necessary for being a
monkey.
27. I do not sleep soundly if I drink coffee or eat
chocolate.
28. I sleep soundly if I do not drink coffee or eat
chocolate.
29. Your check is not accepted if you do not have a drivers
license or a credit card.
30. Your check is accepted if you have a drivers license or
a credit card.
31. If you drink and drive, you are fined or you go to jail.
c. All dogs are four-legged animals.
d. No sleeping bag is waterproof.
6. Write a sentence that represents the negation of each
statement.
a. She is not a vegetarian.
b. Some elephants are pink.
c. All candy promotes tooth decay.
d. No lunch is free.
7. Using the symbolic representations
p: The lyrics are controversial.
q: The performance is banned.
express the following compound statements in sym-
bolic form.
a. The lyrics are controversial, and the performance is
banned.
b. If the lyrics are not controversial, the performance
is not banned.
c. It is not the case that the lyrics are controversial or
the performance is banned.
d. The lyrics are controversial, and the performance is
not banned.
e. Having controversial lyrics is sufficient for banning
a performance.
f. Noncontroversial lyrics are necessary for not ban-
ning a performance.
8. Using the symbolic representations
p: The food is spicy.
q: The food is aromatic.
express the following compound statements in sym-
bolic form.
a. The food is aromatic and spicy.
b. If the food isn’t spicy, it isn’t aromatic.
c. The food is spicy, and it isn’t aromatic.
d. The food isn’t spicy or aromatic.
e. Being nonaromatic is sufficient for food to be
nonspicy.
f. Being spicy is necessary for food to be aromatic.
9. Using the symbolic representations
p: A person plays the guitar.
q: A person rides a motorcycle.
r: A person wears a leather jacket.
express the following compound statements in sym-
bolic form.
a. If a person plays the guitar or rides a motorcycle,
then the person wears a leather jacket.
b. A person plays the guitar, rides a motorcycle, and
wears a leather jacket.
c. A person wears a leather jacket and doesn’t play the
guitar or ride a motorcycle.
d. All motorcycle riders wear leather jackets.
e. Not wearing a leather jacket is sufficient for not
playing the guitar or riding a motorcycle.
28 CHAPTER 1 Logic
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 28
Property
If the food isn’t spicy, it isn’t aromatic.
Property
If the food isn’t spicy, it isn’t aromatic.
The food is spicy, and it isn’t aromatic.
Property
The food is spicy, and it isn’t aromatic.
The food isn’t spicy or aromatic.
Property
The food isn’t spicy or aromatic.
Being nonaromatic is sufficient for food to be
Property
Being nonaromatic is sufficient for food to be
Being spicy is necessary for food to be aromatic.
Property
Being spicy is necessary for food to be aromatic.
Using the symbolic representations
Property
Using the symbolic representations
A person plays the guitar.
Property
A person plays the guitar.
of
express the following compound statements in sym-
of
express the following compound statements in sym-
Cengage
In Exercises 11–34, translate the sentence into symbolic form. Be
Cengage
In Exercises 11–34, translate the sentence into symbolic form. Be
sure to define each letter you use. (More than one answer is
Cengage
sure to define each letter you use. (More than one answer is
possible.)
Cengage
possible.)
11.
Cengage
11.
All squares are rectangles.
Cengage
All squares are rectangles.
12.
Cengage
12.
All people born in the United States are American
Cengage
All people born in the United States are American
citizens.
Cengage
citizens.
13.
Cengage
13.
14.
Cengage
14.
Learning
If the car does not cost $70,000, it does not go
Learning
If the car does not cost $70,000, it does not go
The car is red and it does not go 140 mph or cost
Learning
The car is red and it does not go 140 mph or cost
Being able to go 140 mph is sufficient for a car to
Learning
Being able to go 140 mph is sufficient for a car to
cost $70,000 or be red.
Learning
cost $70,000 or be red.
Not being red is necessary for a car to cost $70,000
Learning
Not being red is necessary for a car to cost $70,000
and not go 140 mph.
Learning
and not go 140 mph.
In Exercises 11–34, translate the sentence into symbolic form. Be
Learning
In Exercises 11–34, translate the sentence into symbolic form. Be
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
43. What is a negation? 44. What is a conjunction?
45. What is a disjunction? 46. What is a conditional?
47. What is a sufficient condition?
48. What is a necessary condition?
49. What is the difference between the inclusive or and the
exclusive or?
50. Create a sentence that is a self-contradiction, or para-
dox, as in part (e) of Example 1.
History Questions
51. In what academic field did Gottfried Leibniz receive his
degrees? Why is the study of logic important in this field?
52. Who developed a formal system of logic based on syl-
logistic arguments?
53. What is meant by characteristica universalis? Who
proposed this theory?
Exercises 54–58 refer to the following: A culinary institute has a
small restaurant in which the students prepare various dishes.
The menu changes daily, and during a specific week, the following
dishes are to be prepared: moussaka, pilaf, quiche, ratatouille,
stroganoff, and teriyaki. During the week, the restaurant does
not prepare any other kind of dish. The selection of dishes the
restaurant offers is consistent with the following conditions:
If the restaurant offers pilaf, then it does not offer ratatouille.
If the restaurant does not offer stroganoff, then it offers pilaf.
If the restaurant offers quiche, then it offers both ratatouille and
teriyaki.
If the restaurant offers teriyaki, then it offers moussaka or
stroganoff or both.
54. Which one of the following could be a complete and
accurate list of the dishes the restaurant offers on a
specific day?
a. pilaf, quiche, ratatouille, teriyaki
b. quiche, stroganoff, teriyaki
THE NEXT LEVEL
If a person wants to pursue an advanced degree
(something beyond a bachelors or four-year
degree), chances are the person must take a stan-
dardized exam to gain admission to a graduate
school or to be admitted into a specific program.
These exams are intended to measure verbal,
quantitative, and analytical skills that have devel-
oped throughout a person’s life. Many classes and
study guides are available to help people prepare
for the exams. The following questions are typical
of those found in the study guides.
32. If you are rich and famous, you have many friends and
enemies.
33. You get a refund or a store credit if the product is
defective.
34. The streets are slippery if it is raining or snowing.
35. Using the symbolic representations
p: I am an environmentalist.
q: I recycle my aluminum cans.
express the following in words.
a. p q b. p q
c. q p d. q p
36. Using the symbolic representations
p: I am innocent.
q: I have an alibi.
express the following in words.
a. p q b. p q
c. q p d. q p
37. Using the symbolic representations
p: I am an environmentalist.
q: I recycle my aluminum cans.
r: I recycle my newspapers.
express the following in words.
a. (q r) p b. p (q r)
c. (q r) p d. (r q) p
38. Using the symbolic representations
p: I am innocent.
q: I have an alibi.
r: I go to jail.
express the following in words.
a. (p q) r b. (p q) r
c. (p q) r d. (p r) q
39. Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Explain why.
Statement #1: “Cold weather is necessary for it to
snow.”
Statement #2: “Cold weather is sufficient for it to snow.”
40. Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Explain why.
Statement #1: “Being cloudy is necessary for it to rain.”
Statement #2: “Being cloudy is sufficient for it to rain.”
41. Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Explain why.
Statement #1: “Having 31 days in a month is necessary
for it not to be February.”
Statement #2: “Having 31 days in a month is sufficient
for it not to be February.”
42. Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Explain why.
Statement #1: “Being the Fourth of July is necessary
for the U.S. Post Office to be closed.”
Statement #2: “Being the Fourth of July is sufficient
for the U.S. Post Office to be closed.”
1.2 Exercises 29
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 29
Property
(
Property
(
p
Property
p
(p(
Property
(p(
Property
d.
Property
d.
(
Property
(
p
Property
p
(p(
Property
(p(
Property
r
Property
r
)
Property
)
Property
Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Property
Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Statement #1: “Cold weather is necessary for it to
Property
Statement #1: “Cold weather is necessary for it to
Statement #2: “Cold weather is sufficient for it to snow.”
Property
Statement #2: “Cold weather is sufficient for it to snow.”
Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Property
Which statement, #1 or #2, is more appropriate?
Explain why.
Property
Explain why.
of
q
of
q
)
of
)
of
Cengage
logistic arguments?
Cengage
logistic arguments?
53.
Cengage
53.
What is meant by
Cengage
What is meant by
proposed this theory?
Cengage
proposed this theory?
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
Create a sentence that is a self-contradiction, or para-
Learning
Create a sentence that is a self-contradiction, or para-
dox, as in part (e) of Example 1.
Learning
dox, as in part (e) of Example 1.
History Questions
Learning
History Questions
In what academic field did Gottfried Leibniz receive his
Learning
In what academic field did Gottfried Leibniz receive his
degrees? Why is the study of logic important in this field?
Learning
degrees? Why is the study of logic important in this field?
Who developed a formal system of logic based on syl-
Learning
Who developed a formal system of logic based on syl-
logistic arguments?
Learning
logistic arguments?
What is meant by
Learning
What is meant by
57. If the restaurant does not offer teriyaki, then which one
of the following must be true?
a. The restaurant offers pilaf.
b. The restaurant offers at most three different dishes.
c. The restaurant offers at least two different dishes.
d. The restaurant offers neither quiche nor ratatouille.
e. The restaurant offers neither quiche nor pilaf.
58. If the restaurant offers teriyaki, then which one of the
following must be false?
a. The restaurant does not offer moussaka.
b. The restaurant does not offer ratatouille.
c. The restaurant does not offer stroganoff.
d. The restaurant offers ratatouille but not quiche.
e. The restaurant offers ratatouille but not stroganoff.
c. quiche, ratatouille, teriyaki
d. ratatouille, stroganoff
e. quiche, ratatouille
55. Which one of the following cannot be a complete and
accurate list of the dishes the restaurant offers on a spe-
cific day?
a. moussaka, pilaf, quiche, ratatouille, teriyaki
b. quiche, ratatouille, stroganoff, teriyaki
c. moussaka, pilaf, teriyaki
d. stroganoff, teriyaki
e. pilaf, stroganoff
56. Which one of the following could be the only kind of
dish the restaurant offers on a specific day?
a. teriyaki b. stroganoff
c. ratatouille d. quiche
e. moussaka
30 CHAPTER 1 Logic
1.3 Truth Tables
Objectives
Construct a truth table for a compound statement
Determine whether two statements are equivalent
Apply De Morgan’s Laws
Suppose your friend Maria is a doctor, and you know that she is a Democrat. If
someone told you, “Maria is a doctor and a Republican,” you would say that the
statement was false. On the other hand, if you were told, “Maria is a doctor or a
Republican,” you would say that the statement was true. Each of these state-
ments is a compound statement—the result of joining individual statements
with connective words. When is a compound statement true, and when is it
false? To answer these questions, we must examine whether the individual
statements are true or false and the manner in which the statements are
connected.
The truth value of a statement is the classification of the statement as true
or false and is denoted by T or F. For example, the truth value of the statement
“Santa Fe is the capital of New Mexico” is T. (The statement is true.) In contrast,
the truth value of “Memphis is the capital of Tennessee” is F. (The statement is
false.)
A convenient way of determining whether a compound statement is true or
false is to construct a truth table. A truth table is a listing of all possible combina-
tions of the individual statements as true or false, along with the resulting truth
value of the compound statement. As we will see, truth tables also allow us to dis-
tinguish valid arguments from invalid arguments.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 30
Property
Construct a truth table for a compound statement
Property
Construct a truth table for a compound statement
Determine whether two statements are equivalent
Property
Determine whether two statements are equivalent
Apply De Morgan’s Laws
Property
Apply De Morgan’s Laws
Suppose your friend Maria is a doctor, and you know that she is a Democrat. If
Property
Suppose your friend Maria is a doctor, and you know that she is a Democrat. If
someone told you, “Maria is a doctor and a Republican,” you would say that the
Property
someone told you, “Maria is a doctor and a Republican,” you would say that the
statement was false. On the other hand, if you were told, “Maria is a doctor or a
Property
statement was false. On the other hand, if you were told, “Maria is a doctor or a
of
Construct a truth table for a compound statement
of
Construct a truth table for a compound statement
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
The restaurant does not offer stroganoff.
Learning
The restaurant does not offer stroganoff.
The restaurant offers ratatouille but not quiche.
Learning
The restaurant offers ratatouille but not quiche.
The restaurant offers ratatouille but not stroganoff.
Learning
The restaurant offers ratatouille but not stroganoff.
The Negation p
The negation of a statement is the denial, or opposite, of the statement. (As was
stated in the previous section, because the truth value of the negation depends on the
truth value of the original statement, a negation can be classified as a compound
statement.) To construct the truth table for the negation of a statement, we must first
examine the original statement. A statement p may be true or false, as shown in
Figure 1.31. If the statement p is true, the negation p is false; if p is false, p is
true. The truth table for the compound statement p is given in Figure 1.32. Row 1
of the table is read “p is false when p is true.” Row 2 is read “p is true when
p is false.”
The Conjunction p q
A conjunction is the joining of two statements with the word and. The compound
statement “Maria is a doctor and a Republican” is a conjunction with the following
symbolic representation:
p: Maria is a doctor.
q: Maria is a Republican.
p q: Maria is a doctor and a Republican.
The truth value of a compound statement depends on the truth values of the
individual statements that make it up. How many rows will the truth table for the
conjunction p q contain? Because p has two possible truth values (T or F) and
q has two possible truth values (T or F), we need four (2 · 2) rows in order to list
all possible combinations of Ts and Fs, as shown in Figure 1.33.
For the conjunction p q to be true, the components p and q must both be
true; the conjunction is false otherwise. The completed truth table for the conjunc-
tion p q is given in Figure 1.34. The symbols p and q can be replaced by any state-
ments. The table gives the truth value of the statement p and q,” dependent upon
the truth values of the individual statements p and q. For instance, row 3 is read
“The conjunction p q is false when p is false and q is true.” The other rows are
read in a similar manner.
The Disjunction p q
A disjunction is the joining of two statements with the word or. The compound
statement “Maria is a doctor or a Republican” is a disjunction (the inclusive or)
with the following symbolic representation:
p: Maria is a doctor.
q: Maria is a Republican.
p q: Maria is a doctor or a Republican.
Even though your friend Maria the doctor is not a Republican, the disjunction
“Maria is a doctor or a Republican” is true. For a disjunction to be true, at least one
of the components must be true. A disjunction is false only when both components
are false. The truth table for the disjunction p q is given in Figure 1.35.
1.3 Truth Tables 31
Truth values for a statement p.
FIGURE 1.31
p
T
F
1.
2.
Truth table for a negation p.
FIGURE 1.32
p ~p
TF
FT
1.
2.
Truth values for two statements.
FIGURE 1.33
pq
TT
TF
FT
FF
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for a conjunction
p q.
FIGURE 1.34
pqpq
TT T
TF F
FT F
FF F
1.
2.
3.
4.
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for a disjunction
p q.
FIGURE 1.35
pqp
q
TT T
TF T
FT T
FF F
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 31
Property
true; the conjunction is false otherwise. The completed truth table for the conjunc-
Property
true; the conjunction is false otherwise. The completed truth table for the conjunc-
tion
Property
tion
p
Property
p
ments. The table gives the truth value of the statement
Property
ments. The table gives the truth value of the statement
the truth values of the individual statements
Property
the truth values of the individual statements
“The conjunction
Property
“The conjunction
Truth table for a conjunction
Property
Truth table for a conjunction
Property
of
has two possible truth values (T or F), we need four (2
of
has two possible truth values (T or F), we need four (2
all possible combinations of Ts and Fs, as shown in Figure 1.33.
of
all possible combinations of Ts and Fs, as shown in Figure 1.33.
For the conjunction
of
For the conjunction
true; the conjunction is false otherwise. The completed truth table for the conjunc-
of
true; the conjunction is false otherwise. The completed truth table for the conjunc-
Cengage
Maria is a Republican.
Cengage
Maria is a Republican.
Maria is a doctor and a Republican.
Cengage
Maria is a doctor and a Republican.
The truth value of a compound statement depends on the truth values of the
Cengage
The truth value of a compound statement depends on the truth values of the
individual statements that make it up. How many rows will the truth table for the
Cengage
individual statements that make it up. How many rows will the truth table for the
conjunction
Cengage
conjunction
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
contain? Because
Cengage
contain? Because
has two possible truth values (T or F), we need four (2
Cengage
has two possible truth values (T or F), we need four (2
all possible combinations of Ts and Fs, as shown in Figure 1.33.
Cengage
all possible combinations of Ts and Fs, as shown in Figure 1.33.
For the conjunction
Cengage
For the conjunction
Learning
is the joining of two statements with the word
Learning
is the joining of two statements with the word
statement “Maria is a doctor and a Republican” is a conjunction with the following
Learning
statement “Maria is a doctor and a Republican” is a conjunction with the following
EXAMPLE 1 CONSTRUCTING A TRUTH TABLE Under what specific conditions is the
following compound statement true? “I have a high school diploma, or I have a
full-time job and no high school diploma.”
SOLUTION First, we translate the statement into symbolic form, and then we construct the
truth table for the symbolic expression. Define p and q as
p: I have a high school diploma.
q: I have a full-time job.
The given statement has the symbolic representation p (q p).
Because there are two letters, we need 2 2 4 rows. We need to insert a col-
umn for each connective in the symbolic expression p (q p). As in algebra,
we start inside any grouping symbols and work our way out. Therefore, we need a
column for p, a column for q p, and a column for the entire expression
p (q p), as shown in Figure 1.36.
32 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Required columns in the truth table.FIGURE 1.36
1.
2.
3.
4.
pq~pq~pp(q ~p)
TT
TF
FT
FF
In the p column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for p. Next, the
conjunction q p is true only when both components are true; enter a T in row 3
and Fs elsewhere. Finally, the disjunction p (q p) is false only when both
components p and (q p) are false; enter an F in row 4 and Ts elsewhere. The
completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.37.
pq~pq~pp(q ~p)
TT F F T
TF F F T
FT T T T
FF T F F
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for p (q p).FIGURE 1.37
As is indicated in the truth table, the symbolic expression p (q p) is true
under all conditions except one: row 4; the expression is false when both p and q
are false. Therefore, the statement “I have a high school diploma, or I have a full-
time job and no high school diploma” is true in every case except when the speaker
has no high school diploma and no full-time job.
If the symbolic representation of a compound statement consists of two
different letters, its truth table will have 2 2 4 rows. How many rows are re-
quired if a compound statement consists of three letters—say, p, q, and r? Because
each statement has two possible truth values (T and F), the truth table must contain
2 2 2 8 rows. In general, each time a new statement is added, the number of
rows doubles.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 32
Property
completed truth
Property
completed truth
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
Property
TT F F T
Property
TT F F T
Property
TF F F T
Property
TF F F T
Property
1.
Property
1.
2.
Property
2.
3.
Property
3.
Property
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
TT F F T
Property
TT F F T
Property
Property
of
and Fs elsewhere. Finally, the disjunction
of
and Fs elsewhere. Finally, the disjunction
components
of
components
p
of
p
and (
of
and (
q
of
q
completed truth
of
completed truth
table is shown in Figure 1.37.
of
table is shown in Figure 1.37.
Cengage
Required columns in the truth table.
Cengage
Required columns in the truth table.
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for
Cengage
column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for
p
Cengage
p
is true only when both components are true; enter a T in row 3
Cengage
is true only when both components are true; enter a T in row 3
and Fs elsewhere. Finally, the disjunction
Cengage
and Fs elsewhere. Finally, the disjunction
Learning
Learning
p
Learning
p
). As in algebra,
Learning
). As in algebra,
we start inside any grouping symbols and work our way out. Therefore, we need a
Learning
we start inside any grouping symbols and work our way out. Therefore, we need a
, and a column for the entire expression
Learning
, and a column for the entire expression
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
EXAMPLE 2 CONSTRUCTING A TRUTH TABLE Under what specific conditions is the
following compound statement true? “I own a handgun, and it is not the case that
I am a criminal or police officer.”
SOLUTION First, we translate the statement into symbolic form, and then we construct the truth
table for the symbolic expression. Define the three simple statements as follows:
p: I own a handgun.
q: I am a criminal.
r: I am a police officer.
The given statement has the symbolic representation p (q r). Since there are
three letters, we need 2
3
8 rows. We start with three columns, one for each letter.
To account for all possible combinations of p, q, and r as true or false, proceed as
follows:
1. Fill the first half (four rows) of column 1 with Ts and the rest with Fs, as shown in
Figure 1.38(a).
2. In the next column, split each half into halves, the first half receiving Ts and the second
Fs. In other words, alternate two Ts and two Fs in column 2, as shown in Fig-
ure 1.38(b).
3. Again, split each half into halves; the first half receives Ts, and the second half receives
Fs. Because we are dealing with the third (last) column, the Ts and Fs will alternate, as
shown in Figure 1.38(c).
1.3 Truth Tables 33
pqr
T
T
T
T
F
F
F
F
pqr
TT
TT
TF
TF
FT
FT
FF
FF
pqr
TTT
TTF
TFT
TFF
FTT
FTF
FFT
FFF
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
(a)
(b)(c)
Truth values for three statements.FIGURE 1.38
(This process of filling the first half of the first column with Ts and the second half
with Fs and then splitting each half into halves with blocks of Ts and Fs applies to
all truth tables.)
We need to insert a column for each connective in the symbolic expression
p (q r), as shown in Figure 1.39.
NUMBER OF ROWS
If a compound statement consists of n individual statements, each represented
by a different letter, the number of rows required in its truth table is 2
n
.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 33
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
1.
Property
1.
Property
of
shown in Figure 1.38(c).
of
shown in Figure 1.38(c).
of
of
Cengage
Fill the first half (four rows) of column 1 with Ts and the rest with Fs, as shown in
Cengage
Fill the first half (four rows) of column 1 with Ts and the rest with Fs, as shown in
In the next column, split each half into halves, the first half receiving Ts and the second
Cengage
In the next column, split each half into halves, the first half receiving Ts and the second
Fs. In other words, alternate two Ts and two Fs in column 2, as shown in Fig-
Cengage
Fs. In other words, alternate two Ts and two Fs in column 2, as shown in Fig-
Again, split each half into halves; the first half receives Ts, and the second half receives
Cengage
Again, split each half into halves; the first half receives Ts, and the second half receives
Fs. Because we are dealing with the third (last) column, the Ts and Fs will alternate, as
Cengage
Fs. Because we are dealing with the third (last) column, the Ts and Fs will alternate, as
shown in Figure 1.38(c).
Cengage
shown in Figure 1.38(c).
Learning
First, we translate the statement into symbolic form, and then we construct the truth
Learning
First, we translate the statement into symbolic form, and then we construct the truth
table for the symbolic expression. Define the three simple statements as follows:
Learning
table for the symbolic expression. Define the three simple statements as follows:
The given statement has the symbolic representation
Learning
The given statement has the symbolic representation
8 rows. We start with three columns, one for each letter.
Learning
8 rows. We start with three columns, one for each letter.
To account for all possible combinations of
Learning
To account for all possible combinations of
p, q,
Learning
p, q,
34 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Required columns in the truth table.FIGURE 1.39
p q r q r ~(q r) p ~(q r)
TTT
TTF
TFT
TFF
FTT
FTF
FFT
FFF
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
p q r q r ~(q r) p ~(q r)
TTT T F F
TTF T F F
TFT T F F
TFF F T T
FTT T F F
FTF T F F
FFT T F F
FFF F T F
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
p q r q r ~(q r) p ~(q r)
TTT T F
TTF T F
TFT T F
TFF F T
FTT T F
FTF T F
FFT T F
FFF F T
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
Truth values of the expressions q r and ~(q r).FIGURE 1.40
Truth table for p (q r).FIGURE 1.41
Now fill in the appropriate symbol in the column under q r. Enter F if both
q and r are false; enter T otherwise (that is, if at least one is true). In the (q r)
column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for q r, as in Figure 1.40.
The conjunction p (q r) is true only when both p and (q r) are true;
enter a T in row 4 and Fs elsewhere. The truth table is shown in Figure 1.41.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 34
Property
Property
FFT T F
Property
FFT T F
FFF F T
Property
FFF F T
Property
Property
Property
FFT T F
Property
FFT T F
Property
FFF F T
Property
FFF F T
Property
Property
FIGURE 1.40
Property
FIGURE 1.40
enter a T in row 4 and Fs elsewhere. The truth table is shown in Figure 1.41.
Property
enter a T in row 4 and Fs elsewhere. The truth table is shown in Figure 1.41.
Property
of
of
of
FTF T F
of
FTF T F
of
FFT T F
of
FFT T F
of
of
of
FTF T F
of
FTF T F
FFT T F
of
FFT T F
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
Cengage
r
Cengage
r
)
Cengage
)
Cengage
TTT T F
Cengage
TTT T F
Cengage
TTF T F
Cengage
TTF T F
Cengage
TFT T F
Cengage
TFT T F
Cengage
TFF F T
Cengage
TFF F T
Cengage
FTT T F
Cengage
FTT T F
FTF T F
Cengage
FTF T F
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
TTF T F
Cengage
TTF T F
Cengage
TFT T F
Cengage
TFT T F
TFF F T
Cengage
TFF F T
Cengage
Cengage
TFF F T
Cengage
TFF F T
Cengage
FTT T F
Cengage
FTT T F
FTF T F
Cengage
FTF T F
Learning
Learning
p
Learning
p
Learning
Learning
Now fill in the appropriate symbol in the column under
Learning
Now fill in the appropriate symbol in the column under
q
Learning
q
are false; enter T otherwise (that is, if at least one is true). In the
Learning
are false; enter T otherwise (that is, if at least one is true). In the
column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for
Learning
column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for
q
Learning
q
Learning
As indicated in the truth table, the expression p (q r) is true only when
p is true and both q and r are false. Therefore, the statement “I own a handgun, and
it is not the case that I am a criminal or police officer” is true only when the speaker
owns a handgun, is not a criminal, and is not a police officer—in other words, the
speaker is a law-abiding citizen who owns a handgun.
The Conditional p q
A conditional is a compound statement of the form “If p, then q” and is symbol-
ized p q. Under what circumstances is a conditional true, and when is it false?
Consider the following (compound) statement: “If you give me $50, then I will give
you a ticket to the ballet.” This statement is a conditional and has the following
representation:
p: You give me $50.
q: I give you a ticket to the ballet.
p q: If you give me $50, then I will give you a ticket to the ballet.
The conditional can be viewed as a promise: If you give me $50, then I will
give you a ticket to the ballet. Suppose you give me $50; that is, suppose p is true.
I have two options: Either I give you a ticket to the ballet (q is true), or I do not (q is
false). If I do give you the ticket, the conditional p q is true (I have kept my
promise); if I do not give you the ticket, the conditional p q is false (I have not
kept my promise). These situations are shown in rows 1 and 2 of the truth table in
Figure 1.42. Rows 3 and 4 require further analysis.
Suppose you do not give me $50; that is, suppose p is false. Whether or not I
give you a ticket, you cannot say that I broke my promise; that is, you cannot say that
the conditional p q is false. Consequently, since a statement is either true or false,
the conditional is labeled true (by default). In other words, when the premise p of a
conditional is false, it does not matter whether the conclusion q is true or false. In
both cases, the conditional p q is automatically labeled true, because it is not false.
The completed truth table for a conditional is given in Figure 1.43. Notice
that the only circumstance under which a conditional is false is when the premise
p is true and the conclusion q is false, as shown in row 2.
EXAMPLE 3 CONSTRUCTING A TRUTH TABLE Under what conditions is the symbolic
expression q p true?
SOLUTION Our truth table has 2
2
4 rows and contains a column for p, q, p, and q p,
as shown in Figure 1.44.
1.3 Truth Tables 35
pqpq
TT T
TF F
FT ?
FF ?
1.
2.
3.
4.
What if p is false?
FIGURE 1.42
p q p q
TT T
TF F
FT T
FF T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for p q.
FIGURE 1.43
pq~pq~p
TT
TF
FT
FF
1.
2.
3.
4.
pq~pq~p
TT F F
TF F T
FT T T
FF T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Required columns in the
truth table.
FIGURE 1.44
Truth table for q p.FIGURE 1.45
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 35
Property
both cases, the conditional
Property
both cases, the conditional
The completed truth table for a conditional is given in Figure 1.43. Notice
Property
The completed truth table for a conditional is given in Figure 1.43. Notice
that the only circumstance under which a conditional is false is when the premise
Property
that the only circumstance under which a conditional is false is when the premise
p
Property
p
is true and the conclusion
Property
is true and the conclusion
EXAMPLE
Property
EXAMPLE
3
Property
3
of
the conditional is labeled true (by default). In other words, when the premise
of
the conditional is labeled true (by default). In other words, when the premise
conditional is false, it does not matter whether the conclusion
of
conditional is false, it does not matter whether the conclusion
both cases, the conditional
of
both cases, the conditional
The completed truth table for a conditional is given in Figure 1.43. Notice
of
The completed truth table for a conditional is given in Figure 1.43. Notice
Cengage
The conditional can be viewed as a promise:
Cengage
The conditional can be viewed as a promise:
give you a ticket to the ballet. Suppose you give me $50; that is, suppose
Cengage
give you a ticket to the ballet. Suppose you give me $50; that is, suppose
I have two options: Either I give you a ticket to the ballet (
Cengage
I have two options: Either I give you a ticket to the ballet (
false). If I do give you the ticket, the conditional
Cengage
false). If I do give you the ticket, the conditional
promise); if I do not give you the ticket, the conditional
Cengage
promise); if I do not give you the ticket, the conditional
kept my promise). These situations are
Cengage
kept my promise). These situations are
Figure 1.42. Rows 3 and 4 require further analysis.
Cengage
Figure 1.42. Rows 3 and 4 require further analysis.
Suppose you do not give me $50; that is, suppose
Cengage
Suppose you do not give me $50; that is, suppose
give you a ticket, you cannot say that I broke my promise; that is, you cannot say that
Cengage
give you a ticket, you cannot say that I broke my promise; that is, you cannot say that
the conditional
Cengage
the conditional
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
the conditional is labeled true (by default). In other words, when the premise
Cengage
the conditional is labeled true (by default). In other words, when the premise
conditional is false, it does not matter whether the conclusion
Cengage
conditional is false, it does not matter whether the conclusion
Learning
Under what circumstances is a conditional true, and when is it false?
Learning
Under what circumstances is a conditional true, and when is it false?
following (compound) statement: “If you give me $50, then I will give
Learning
following (compound) statement: “If you give me $50, then I will give
you a ticket to the ballet.” This statement is a conditional and has the following
Learning
you a ticket to the ballet.” This statement is a conditional and has the following
If you give me $50, then I will give you a ticket to the ballet.
Learning
If you give me $50, then I will give you a ticket to the ballet.
The conditional can be viewed as a promise:
Learning
The conditional can be viewed as a promise:
give you a ticket to the ballet. Suppose you give me $50; that is, suppose
Learning
give you a ticket to the ballet. Suppose you give me $50; that is, suppose
In the p column, fill in truth values that are opposite those for p. Now, a
conditional is false only when its premise (in this case, q) is true and its conclusion
(in this case, p) is false. Therefore, q p is false only in row 1; the conditional
q p is true under all conditions except the condition that both p and q are true.
The completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.45.
EXAMPLE 4 CONSTRUCTING A TRUTH TABLE Construct a truth table for the follow-
ing compound statement: “I walk up the stairs if I want to exercise or if the elevator
isn’t working.”
SOLUTION Rewriting the statement so the word if is first, we have “If I want to exercise or (if)
the elevator isn’t working, then I walk up the stairs.”
Now we must translate the statement into symbols and construct a truth table.
Define the following:
p: I want to exercise.
q: The elevator is working.
r: I walk up the stairs.
The statement now has the symbolic representation (p q) r. Because we
have three letters, our table must have 2
3
8 rows. Inserting a column for each
letter and a column for each connective, we have the initial setup shown in
Figure 1.46.
36 CHAPTER 1 Logic
pqr~q p ~q (p ~q) r
TTT
TTF
TFT
TFF
FTT
FTF
FFT
FFF
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
Required columns in the truth table.FIGURE 1.46
In the column labeled q, enter truth values that are the opposite of those
of q. Next, enter the truth values of the disjunction p q in column 5. Recall that
a disjunction is false only when both components are false and is true otherwise.
Consequently, enter Fs in rows 5 and 6 (since both p and q are false) and Ts in
the remaining rows, as shown in Figure 1.47.
The last column involves a conditional; it is false only when its premise is true
and its conclusion is false. Therefore, enter Fs in rows 2, 4, and 8 (since p q is
true and r is false) and Ts in the remaining rows. The truth table is shown in
Figure 1.48.
As Figure 1.48 shows, the statement “I walk up the stairs if I want to exercise
or if the elevator isn’t working” is true in all situations except those listed in rows
2, 4, and 8. For instance, the statement is false (row 8) when the speaker does not
want to exercise, the elevator is not working, and the speaker does not walk up the
stairs—in other words, the speaker stays on the ground floor of the building when
the elevator is broken.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 36
Property
Property
TFF
Property
TFF
Property
FTT
Property
FTT
Property
FTF
Property
FTF
Property
FFT
Property
FFT
Property
6.
Property
6.
7.
Property
7.
8
Property
8
.
Property
.
Property
Property
TFF
Property
TFF
Property
FTT
Property
FTT
Property
FTF
Property
FTF
Property
Property
of
of
of
TFT
of
TFT
TFF
of
TFF
of
of
of
TFT
of
TFT
TFF
of
TFF
Cengage
The statement now has the symbolic representation (
Cengage
The statement now has the symbolic representation (
have three letters, our table must have 2
Cengage
have three letters, our table must have 2
3
Cengage
3
Cengage
8 rows. Inserting a column for each
Cengage
8 rows. Inserting a column for each
letter and a column for each connective, we have the initial setup shown in
Cengage
letter and a column for each connective, we have the initial setup shown in
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
~
Cengage
~
q p
Cengage
q p
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
TTF
Cengage
TTF
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
q p
Cengage
q p
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
is first, we have “If I want to exercise or (if)
Learning
is first, we have “If I want to exercise or (if)
Now we must translate the statement into symbols and construct a truth table.
Learning
Now we must translate the statement into symbols and construct a truth table.
The statement now has the symbolic representation (
Learning
The statement now has the symbolic representation (
1.3 Truth Tables 37
Equivalent Expressions
When you purchase a car, the car is either new or used. If a salesperson told you,
“It is not the case that the car is not new,” what condition would the car be in? This
compound statement consists of one individual statement (“p: The car is new”) and
two negations:
“It is not the case that the car is not new.”
p
Does this mean that the car is new? To answer this question, we will construct a
truth table for the symbolic expression (p) and compare its truth values with
those of the original p. Because there is only one letter, we need 2
1
2 rows, as
shown in Figure 1.49.
We must insert a column for p and a column for (p). Now, p has truth
values that are opposite those of p, and (p) has truth values that are opposite
those of p, as shown in Figure 1.50.
↑↑↑↑
pqr~q p ~q (p ~q) r
TTT F T
TTF F T
TFT T T
TFF T T
FTT F F
FTF F F
FFT T T
FFF T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
Truth values of the expressions.FIGURE 1.47
Truth table for (p q) r.FIGURE 1.48
pqr~q p ~q (p ~q) r
TTT F T T
TTF F T F
TFT T T T
TFF T T F
FTT F F T
FTF F F T
FFT T T T
FFF T T F
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
p
T
F
1.
2.
Truth values of p.
FIGURE 1.49
1.
2.
Truth table for (p).
FIGURE 1.50
p ~p ~(~p)
TF T
FT F
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 37
Property
Property
Property
of
of
FIGURE 1.48
of
FIGURE 1.48
FFF T T F
of
FFF T T F
of
of
FFF T T F
of
FFF T T F
of
Cengage
Cengage
TTF F T F
Cengage
TTF F T F
Cengage
TFT T T T
Cengage
TFT T T T
Cengage
TFF T T F
Cengage
TFF T T F
Cengage
FTT F F T
Cengage
FTT F F T
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
FFT T T T
Cengage
FFT T T T
FFF T T F
Cengage
FFF T T F
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
TFT T T T
Cengage
TFT T T T
Cengage
TFF T T F
Cengage
TFF T T F
FTT F F T
Cengage
FTT F F T
Cengage
Cengage
TFF T T F
Cengage
TFF T T F
Cengage
FTT F F T
Cengage
FTT F F T
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
FTF F F T
Cengage
FFT T T T
Cengage
FFT T T T
FFF T T F
Cengage
FFF T T F
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
(
Learning
(
p
Learning
p
Learning
~
Learning
~
q
Learning
q
)
Learning
)
Learning
TTT F T T
Learning
TTT F T T
TTF F T F
Learning
TTF F T F
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
TTT F T T
Learning
TTT F T T
TTF F T F
Learning
TTF F T F
Notice that the values in the column labeled (p) are identical to those in
the column labeled p. Whenever this happens, the expressions are said to be
equivalent and may be used interchangeably. Therefore, the statement “It is not
the case that the car is not new” is equivalent in meaning to the statement “The
car is new.”
Equivalent expressions are symbolic expressions that have identical truth
values in each corresponding entry. The expression p q is read “p is equiva-
lent to q” or “p and q are equivalent.” As we can see in Figure 1.50, an expres-
sion and its double negation are logically equivalent. This relationship can be
expressed as p (p).
EXAMPLE 5 DETERMINING WHETHER STATEMENTS ARE EQUIVALENT Are the
statements “If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes” and “I am a
homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes” equivalent?
SOLUTION We begin by defining the statements:
p: I am a homeowner.
q: I pay property taxes.
p q: If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes.
p q: I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.
The truth table contains 2
2
4 rows, and the initial setup is shown in Figure 1.51.
Now enter the appropriate truth values under q (the opposite of q). Because
the conjunction p q is true only when both p and q are true, enter a T in row 2
and Fs elsewhere. The conditional p q is false only when p is true and q is false;
therefore, enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. The completed truth table is shown
in Figure 1.52.
Because the entries in the columns labeled p q and p q are not the
same, the statements are not equivalent. “If I am a homeowner, then I pay
property taxes” is not equivalent to “I am a homeowner and I do not pay property
taxes.”
38 CHAPTER 1 Logic
pq~q p ~q p q
TT
TF
FT
FF
1.
2.
3.
4.
Required columns in the
truth table.
FIGURE 1.51
pq~q p ~q p q
TTF F T
TFT T F
FTF F T
FFT F T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for p q.FIGURE 1.52
Notice that the truth values in the columns under p q and p q in Fig-
ure 1.52 are exact opposites; when one is T, the other is F. Whenever this happens,
one statement is the negation of the other. Consequently, p q is the negation of
p q (and vice versa). This can be expressed as p q (p q). The nega-
tion of a conditional is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the premise and the
negation of the conclusion.
Statements that look or sound different may in fact have the same meaning. For
example, “It is not the case that the car is not new” really means the same as “Thecar
is new,” and “It is not the case that if I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes”
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 38
Property
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
Property
TT
Property
TT
Property
1.
Property
1.
2.
Property
2.
3.
Property
3.
Property
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
Property
Property
of
same, the statements are not equivalent. “If I am a homeowner, then I pay
of
same, the statements are not equivalent. “If I am a homeowner, then I pay
property taxes” is
of
property taxes” is
not
of
not
Cengage
If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes.
Cengage
If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes.
I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.
Cengage
I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.
4 rows, and the initial setup is shown in Figure 1.51.
Cengage
4 rows, and the initial setup is shown in Figure 1.51.
Now enter the appropriate truth values under
Cengage
Now enter the appropriate truth values under
is true only when both
Cengage
is true only when both
and Fs elsewhere. The conditional
Cengage
and Fs elsewhere. The conditional
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
therefore, enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. The completed truth table is shown
Cengage
therefore, enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. The completed truth table is shown
Because the entries in the columns labeled
Cengage
Because the entries in the columns labeled
same, the statements are not equivalent. “If I am a homeowner, then I pay
Cengage
same, the statements are not equivalent. “If I am a homeowner, then I pay
equivalent to “I am a homeowner and I do not pay property
Cengage
equivalent to “I am a homeowner and I do not pay property
Learning
DETERMINING WHETHER STATEMENTS ARE EQUIVALENT
Learning
DETERMINING WHETHER STATEMENTS ARE EQUIVALENT
statements “If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes” and “I am a
Learning
statements “If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes” and “I am a
If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes.
Learning
If I am a homeowner, then I pay property taxes.
I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.
Learning
I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.
1.3 Truth Tables 39
GEORGE BOOLE, 1815–1864
Boole’s most influen-
tial work, An Investiga-
tion of the Laws of
Thought, on Which Are
Founded the Mathe-
matical Theories of
Logic and Probabilities,
was published in
1854. In it, he wrote,
“There exist certain
general principles founded in the very na-
ture of language and logic that exhibit
laws as identical in form as with the laws
of the general symbols of algebra.” With
this insight, Boole had taken a big step
into the world of logical reasoning and
abstract mathematical analysis.
Perhaps because of his lack of formal
training, Boole challenged the status quo,
including the Aristotelian assumption that
all logical arguments could be reduced
to syllogistic arguments. In doing so, he
employed symbols to represent concepts,
as did Leibniz, but he also developed
systems of algebraic manipulation to ac-
company these symbols. Thus, Boole’s
creation is a marriage of logic and math-
ematics. However, as is the case with al-
most all new theories, Boole’s symbolic
logic was not met with total approbation.
In particular, one staunch opponent of his
work was Georg Cantor, whose work on
the origins of set theory and the magni-
tude of infinity will be investigated in
Chapter 2.
In the many years since Boole’s
original work was unveiled, various
scholars have modified, improved, gen-
eralized, and extended its central con-
cepts. Today, Boolean algebras are the
essence of computer software and cir-
cuit design. After all, a computer merely
manipulates predefined symbols and
conforms to a set of preassigned alge-
braic commands.
Historical
Note
Through an algebraic manipulation of logical
symbols, Boole revolutionized the age-old study of
logic. His essay The Mathematical Analysis of
Logic laid the foundation for his later book
An Investigation of the Laws of Thought.
Brown University Library
G
eorge Boole is called “the
father of symbolic logic.”
Computer science owes much
to this self-educated mathemati-
cian. Born the son of a poor
shopkeeper in Lincoln, Eng-
land, Boole had very little for-
mal education, and his prospects for ris-
ing above his family’s lower-class status
were dim. Like Leibniz, he taught himself
Latin; at the age of twelve, he translated
an ode of Horace into English, winning
the attention of the local schoolmasters.
(In his day, knowledge of Latin was a
prerequisite to scholarly endeavors and
to becoming a socially accepted gentle-
man.) After that, his academic desires
were encouraged, and at the age of fif-
teen, he began his long teaching ca-
reer. While teaching arithmetic, he stud-
ied advanced mathematics and physics.
In 1849, after nineteen years of
teaching at elementary schools, Boole
received his big break: He was ap-
pointed professor of mathematics at
Queen’s College in the city of Cork,
Ireland. At last, he was able to research
advanced mathematics, and he be-
came recognized as a first-class mathe-
matician. This was a remarkable feat,
considering Boole’s lack of formal train-
ing and degrees.
© CORBIS
actually means the same as “I am a homeowner, and I do not pay property taxes.”
When we are working with equivalent statements, we can substitute either state-
ment for the other without changing the truth value.
De Morgan’s Laws
Earlier in this section, we saw that the negation of a negation is equivalent to the
original statement; that is, (p) p. Another negation “formula” that we dis-
covered was (p q) p q, that is, the negation of a conditional. Can we
find similar “formulas” for the negations of the other basic connectives, namely,
the conjunction and the disjunction? The answer is yes, and the results are credited
to the English mathematician and logician Augustus De Morgan.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 39
Property
advanced mathematics, and he be-
Property
advanced mathematics, and he be-
came recognized as a first-class mathe-
Property
came recognized as a first-class mathe-
matician. This was a remarkable feat,
Property
matician. This was a remarkable feat,
considering Boole’s lack of formal train-
Property
considering Boole’s lack of formal train-
Property
Property
of
ematics. However, as is the case with al-
of
ematics. However, as is the case with al-
most all new theories, Boole’s symbolic
of
most all new theories, Boole’s symbolic
logic was not met with total approbation.
of
logic was not met with total approbation.
In particular, one staunch opponent of his
of
In particular, one staunch opponent of his
Ireland. At last, he was able to research
of
Ireland. At last, he was able to research
Cengage
Perhaps because of his lack of formal
Cengage
Perhaps because of his lack of formal
training, Boole challenged the status quo,
Cengage
training, Boole challenged the status quo,
including the Aristotelian assumption that
Cengage
including the Aristotelian assumption that
logical arguments could be reduced
Cengage
logical arguments could be reduced
to syllogistic arguments. In doing so, he
Cengage
to syllogistic arguments. In doing so, he
employed symbols to represent concepts,
Cengage
employed symbols to represent concepts,
as did Leibniz, but he also developed
Cengage
as did Leibniz, but he also developed
systems of algebraic manipulation to ac-
Cengage
systems of algebraic manipulation to ac-
company these symbols. Thus, Boole’s
Cengage
company these symbols. Thus, Boole’s
creation is a marriage of logic and math-
Cengage
creation is a marriage of logic and math-
ematics. However, as is the case with al-
Cengage
ematics. However, as is the case with al-
most all new theories, Boole’s symbolic
Cengage
most all new theories, Boole’s symbolic
Learning
this insight, Boole had taken a big step
Learning
this insight, Boole had taken a big step
into the world of logical reasoning and
Learning
into the world of logical reasoning and
Perhaps because of his lack of formal
Learning
Perhaps because of his lack of formal
training, Boole challenged the status quo,
Learning
training, Boole challenged the status quo,
manipulates predefined symbols and
Learning
manipulates predefined symbols and
conforms to a set of preassigned alge-
Learning
conforms to a set of preassigned alge-
braic commands.
Learning
braic commands.
Learning
40 CHAPTER 1 Logic
p ~p
TF
FT
pqpq
TT T
TF F
FT F
FF F
pqpq
TT T
TF T
FT T
FF F
p qpq
TT T
TF F
FT T
FF T
Negation
Conjunction Disjunction Conditional
1.
2.
1.
2.
3.
4.
1.
2.
3.
4.
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth tables for the basic connectives.FIGURE 1.53
De Morgan’s Laws are easily verified through the use of truth tables and will
be addressed in the exercises (see Exercises 55 and 56).
EXAMPLE 6 APPLYING D
E MORGAN’S LAWS Using De Morgan’s Laws, find the negation
of each of the following:
a. It is Friday and I receive a paycheck.
b. You are correct or I am crazy.
SOLUTION a. The symbolic representation of “It is Friday and I receive a paycheck” is
p: It is Friday.
q: I receive a paycheck.
p q: It is Friday and I receive a paycheck.
Therefore, the negation is (p q) p q, that is, “It is not Friday or I do not re-
ceive a paycheck.”
b. The symbolic representation of “You are correct or I am crazy” is
p: You are correct.
q: I am crazy.
p q: You are correct or I am crazy.
Therefore, the negation is (p q) p q, that is, “You are not correct and I am
not crazy.”
As we have seen, the truth value of a compound statement depends on the
truth values of the individual statements that make it up. The truth tables of the
basic connectives are summarized in Figure 1.53.
Equivalent statements are statements that have the same meaning. Equivalent
statements for the negations of the basic connectives are given in Figure 1.54.
DE MORGAN’S LAWS
The negation of the conjunction p q is given by (p q) p q.
“Not p and q” is equivalent to “not p or not q.
The negation of the disjunction p q is given by (p q) p q.
“Not p or q” is equivalent to “not p and not q.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 40
Property
p
Property
p
Property
q:
Property
q:
Therefore, the negation is
Property
Therefore, the negation is
not crazy.”
Property
not crazy.”
truth values of the individual statements that make it up. The truth tables of the
Property
truth values of the individual statements that make it up. The truth tables of the
Property
of
You are correct.
of
You are correct.
I am crazy.
of
I am crazy.
You are correct or I am crazy.
of
You are correct or I am crazy.
Cengage
The symbolic representation of “It is Friday and I receive a paycheck” is
Cengage
The symbolic representation of “It is Friday and I receive a paycheck” is
It is Friday and I receive a paycheck.
Cengage
It is Friday and I receive a paycheck.
Therefore, the negation is
Cengage
Therefore, the negation is
Cengage
(
Cengage
(
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
)
Cengage
)
The symbolic representation of “You are correct or I am crazy” is
Cengage
The symbolic representation of “You are correct or I am crazy” is
You are correct.
Cengage
You are correct.
Learning
De Morgan’s Laws are easily verified through the use of truth tables and will
Learning
De Morgan’s Laws are easily verified through the use of truth tables and will
Using De Morgan’s Laws, find the negation
Learning
Using De Morgan’s Laws, find the negation
The symbolic representation of “It is Friday and I receive a paycheck” is
Learning
The symbolic representation of “It is Friday and I receive a paycheck” is
1.3 Exercises 41
1. ~(~p) p the negation of a negation
2. ~(p q) ~p ~q the negation of a conjunction
3. ~(p q) ~p ~q the negation of a disjunction
4. ~(p q) p ~q the negation of a conditional
Negations of the basic connectives.FIGURE 1.54
1.3
Exercises
In Exercises 1–20, construct a truth table for the symbolic
expressions.
1. p q
2. p q
3. p p
4. p p
5. p q
6. p q
7. q p
8. p q
9. (p q) p
10. (p q) q
11. (p q) (p q)
12. (p q) (p q)
13. p (q r)
14. p (q r)
15. p (q r)
16. p (q r)
17. (r p) (q p)
18. (q p) (r p)
19. (p r) (q r)
20. (p r) (q r)
In Exercises 21–40, translate the compound statement into
symbolic form and then construct the truth table for the
expression.
21. If it is raining, then the streets are wet.
22. If the lyrics are not controversial, the performance is
not banned.
23. The water supply is rationed if it does not rain.
24. The country is in trouble if he is elected.
25. All squares are rectangles.
26. All muscle cars from the Sixties are polluters.
27. No square is a triangle.
28. No electric-powered car is a polluter.
29. Being a monkey is sufficient for not being an ape.
30. Being a chimpanzee is sufficient for not being a monkey.
31. Not being a monkey is necessary for being an ape.
32. Not being a chimpanzee is necessary for being a monkey.
33. Your check is accepted if you have a drivers license or
a credit card.
34. Yougetarefundorastorecreditiftheproductisdefective.
35. If leaded gasoline is used, the catalytic converter is
damaged and the air is polluted.
36. If he does not go to jail, he is innocent or has an alibi.
37. I have a college degree and I do not have a job or own
a house.
38. I surf the Internet and I make purchases and do not pay
sales tax.
39. If Proposition A passes and Proposition B does not,
jobs are lost or new taxes are imposed.
40. If Proposition A does not pass and the legislature raises
taxes, the quality of education is lowered and unem-
ployment rises.
In Exercises 41–50, construct a truth table to determine whether
the statements in each pair are equivalent.
41. The streets are wet or it is not raining.
If it is raining, then the streets are wet.
42. The streets are wet or it is not raining.
If the streets are not wet, then it is not raining.
43. He has a high school diploma or he is unemployed.
If he does not have a high school diploma, then he is
unemployed.
44. She is unemployed or she does not have a high school
diploma.
If she is employed, then she does not have a high
school diploma.
45. If handguns are outlawed, then outlaws have handguns.
If outlaws have handguns, then handguns are outlawed.
46. If interest rates continue to fall, then I can afford to buy
a house.
If interest rates do not continue to fall, then I cannot
afford to buy a house.
47. If the spotted owl is on the endangered species list,
then lumber jobs are lost.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/28/10 4:36 PM Page 41
Property
)
Property
)
Property
p
Property
p
)
Property
)
(
Property
(
q
Property
q
Property
Property
r
Property
r
)
Property
)
Property
(
Property
(
q
Property
q
Property
Property
r
Property
r
)
Property
)
In Exercises 21–40, translate the compound statement into
Property
In Exercises 21–40, translate the compound statement into
of
Cengage
Yougetarefundorastorecreditiftheproductisdefective.
Cengage
Yougetarefundorastorecreditiftheproductisdefective.
35.
Cengage
35.
If leaded gasoline is used, the catalytic converter is
Cengage
If leaded gasoline is used, the catalytic converter is
damaged and the air is polluted.
Cengage
damaged and the air is polluted.
36.
Cengage
36.
If he does not go to jail, he is innocent or has an alibi.
Cengage
If he does not go to jail, he is innocent or has an alibi.
37.
Cengage
37.
I have a college degree and I do not have a job or own
Cengage
I have a college degree and I do not have a job or own
Learning
Learning
Being a chimpanzee is sufficient for not being a monkey.
Learning
Being a chimpanzee is sufficient for not being a monkey.
Not being a monkey is necessary for being an ape.
Learning
Not being a monkey is necessary for being an ape.
Not being a chimpanzee is necessary for being a monkey.
Learning
Not being a chimpanzee is necessary for being a monkey.
Your check is accepted if you have a drivers license or
Learning
Your check is accepted if you have a drivers license or
a credit card.
Learning
a credit card.
Yougetarefundorastorecreditiftheproductisdefective.
Learning
Yougetarefundorastorecreditiftheproductisdefective.
If leaded gasoline is used, the catalytic converter is
Learning
If leaded gasoline is used, the catalytic converter is
In Exercises 57–68, write the statement in symbolic form,
construct the negation of the expression (in simplified symbolic
form), and express the negation in words.
57. I have a college degree and I am not employed.
58. It is snowing and classes are canceled.
59. The television set is broken or there is a power outage.
60. The freeway is under construction or I do not ride
the bus.
61. If the building contains asbestos, the original contrac-
tor is responsible.
62. If the legislation is approved, the public is uninformed.
63. The First Amendment has been violated if the lyrics
are censored.
64. Your drivers license is taken away if you do not obey
the laws.
65. Rainy weather is sufficient for not washing my car.
66. Drinking caffeinated coffee is sufficient for not
sleeping.
67. Not talking is necessary for listening.
68. Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
69. a. Under what conditions is a disjunction true?
b. Under what conditions is a disjunction false?
70. a. Under what conditions is a conjunction true?
b. Under what conditions is a conjunction false?
71. a. Under what conditions is a conditional true?
b. Under what conditions is a conditional false?
72. a. Under what conditions is a negation true?
b. Under what conditions is a negation false?
73. What are equivalent expressions?
74. What is a truth table?
75. When constructing a truth table, how do you determine
how many rows to create?
History Questions
76. Who is considered “the father of symbolic logic”?
77. Boolean algebra is a combination of logic and math-
ematics. What is it used for?
If lumber jobs are not lost, then the spotted owl is not
on the endangered species list.
48. If I drink decaffeinated coffee, then I do not stay
awake.
If I do stay awake, then I do not drink decaffeinated
coffee.
49. The plaintiff is innocent or the insurance company
does not settle out of court.
The insurance company settles out of court and the
plaintiff is not innocent.
50. The plaintiff is not innocent and the insurance com-
pany settles out of court.
It is not the case that the plaintiff is innocent or the in-
surance company does not settle out of court.
In Exercises 51–54, construct truth tables to determine which
pairs of statements are equivalent.
51. i. Knowing Morse code is sufficient for operating a
telegraph.
ii. Knowing Morse code is necessary for operating a
telegraph.
iii. Not knowing Morse code is sufficient for not
operating a telegraph.
iv. Not knowing Morse code is necessary for not
operating a telegraph.
52. i. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
ii. Knowing CPR is sufficient for being a paramedic.
iii. Not knowing CPR is necessary for not being a
paramedic.
iv. Not knowing CPR is sufficient for not being a
paramedic.
53. i. The water being cold is necessary for not going
swimming.
ii. The water not being cold is necessary for going
swimming.
iii. The water being cold is sufficient for not going
swimming.
iv. The water not being cold is sufficient for going
swimming.
54. i. The sky not being clear is sufficient for it to be
raining.
ii. The sky being clear is sufficient for it not to be
raining.
iii. Thesky notbeingclearisnecessaryforit toberaining.
iv. Theskybeingclearisnecessaryforitnottoberaining.
55. Using truth tables, verify De Morgan’s Law
(p q) p q.
56. Using truth tables, verify De Morgan’s Law
(p q) p q.
42 CHAPTER 1 Logic
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:34 AM Page 42
Property
The water being cold is necessary for not going
Property
The water being cold is necessary for not going
The water not being cold is necessary for going
Property
The water not being cold is necessary for going
The water being cold is sufficient for not going
Property
The water being cold is sufficient for not going
The water not being cold is sufficient for going
Property
The water not being cold is sufficient for going
The sky not being clear is sufficient for it to be
Property
The sky not being clear is sufficient for it to be
of
Not knowing CPR is sufficient for not being a
of
Not knowing CPR is sufficient for not being a
The water being cold is necessary for not going
of
The water being cold is necessary for not going
Cengage
Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
Cengage
Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
Answer the following questions using complete
Cengage
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Cengage
sentences and your own words.
Cengage
Concept Questions
Cengage
Concept Questions
69. a.
Cengage
69. a.
Not knowing CPR is necessary for not being a
Cengage
Not knowing CPR is necessary for not being a
Not knowing CPR is sufficient for not being a
Cengage
Not knowing CPR is sufficient for not being a
Cengage
Learning
The First Amendment has been violated if the lyrics
Learning
The First Amendment has been violated if the lyrics
Your drivers license is taken away if you do not obey
Learning
Your drivers license is taken away if you do not obey
Rainy weather is sufficient for not washing my car.
Learning
Rainy weather is sufficient for not washing my car.
Drinking caffeinated coffee is sufficient for not
Learning
Drinking caffeinated coffee is sufficient for not
Not talking is necessary for listening.
Learning
Not talking is necessary for listening.
Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
Learning
Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
1.4 More on Conditionals
Objectives
Create the converse, inverse, and contrapositive of a conditional statement
Determine equivalent variations of a conditional statement
Interpret “only if” statements
Interpret a biconditional statement
Conditionals differ from conjunctions and disjunctions with regard to the possibil-
ity of changing the order of the statements. In algebra, the sum x y is equal to the
sum y x; that is, addition is commutative. In everyday language, one realtor might
say, “The house is perfect and the lot is priceless,” while another says, “The lot is
priceless and the house is perfect.” Logically, their meanings are the same, since
(p q) (q p). The order of the components in a conjunction or disjunction makes
no difference in regard to the truth value of the statement. This is not so with
conditionals.
Variations of a Conditional
Given two statements p and q, various “if . . . then . . .” statements can be formed.
EXAMPLE 1 TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS Using the statements
p: You are compassionate.
q: You contribute to charities.
write an “if . . . then . . .” sentence represented by each of the following:
a. p q b. q p c. p q d. q p
SOLUTION a. p q: If you are compassionate, then you contribute to charities.
b. q p: If you contribute to charities, then you are compassionate.
c. p q: If you are not compassionate, then you do not contribute to charities.
d. q p: If you do not contribute to charities, then you are not compassionate.
Each part of Example 1 contains an “if . . . then . . .” statement and is called
a conditional. Any given conditional has three variations: a converse, an inverse,
and a contrapositive. The converse of the conditional “if p then q” is the com-
pound statement “if q then p” That is, we form the converse of the conditional by
interchanging the premise and the conclusion; q p is the converse of p q. The
statement in part (b) of Example 1 is the converse of the statement in part (a).
The inverse of the conditional “if p then q” is the compound statement “if not
p then not q.We form the inverse of the conditional by negating both the premise
and the conclusion; p q is the inverse of p q. The statement in part (c) of
Example 1 is the inverse of the statement in part (a).
The contrapositive of the conditional “if p then q” is the compound
statement “if not q then not p.” We form the contrapositive of the conditional by
43
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 43
Property
q:
Property
q:
write an “if . . . then . . .” sentence represented by each of the following:
Property
write an “if . . . then . . .” sentence represented by each of the following:
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
Property
of
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
of
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
p:
of
p:
You are compassionate.
of
You are compassionate.
Cengage
the truth value of the statement. This is not so with
Cengage
the truth value of the statement. This is not so with
Variations of a Conditional
Cengage
Variations of a Conditional
Given two statements
Cengage
Given two statements
p
Cengage
p
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
Cengage
TRANSLATING SYMBOLS INTO WORDS
Learning
Conditionals differ from conjunctions and disjunctions with regard to the possibil-
Learning
Conditionals differ from conjunctions and disjunctions with regard to the possibil-
ity of changing the order of the statements. In algebra, the sum
Learning
ity of changing the order of the statements. In algebra, the sum
; that is, addition is commutative. In everyday language, one realtor might
Learning
; that is, addition is commutative. In everyday language, one realtor might
say, “The house is perfect and the lot is priceless,” while another says, “The lot is
Learning
say, “The house is perfect and the lot is priceless,” while another says, “The lot is
is perfect.” Logically, their meanings are the same, since
Learning
is perfect.” Logically, their meanings are the same, since
). The order of the components in a conjunction or disjunction makes
Learning
). The order of the components in a conjunction or disjunction makes
the truth value of the statement. This is not so with
Learning
the truth value of the statement. This is not so with
negating and interchanging both the premise and the conclusion; q p is the
contrapositive of p q. The statement in part (d) of Example 1 is the contraposi-
tive of the statement in part (a). The variations of a given conditional are summa-
rized in Figure 1.55. As we will see, some of these variations are equivalent, and
some are not. Unfortunately, many people incorrectly treat them all as equivalent.
44 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Variations of a conditional.FIGURE 1.55
Name Symbolic Form Read As . . .
a (given) conditional p q If p, then q.
the converse (of p q) q p If q, then p.
the inverse (of p q)~p ~q If not p, then not q.
the contrapositive (of p q)~q ~p If not q, then not p.
EXAMPLE 2 CREATING VARIATIONS OFACONDITIONALSTATEMENT Given the
conditional “You did not receive the proper refund if you prepared your own
income tax form,” write the sentence that represents each of the following.
a. the converse of the conditional
b. the inverse of the conditional
c. the contrapositive of the conditional
SOLUTION a. Rewriting the statement in the standard “if . . . then . . .” form, we have the conditional
“If you prepared your own income tax form, then you did not receive the proper re-
fund.” The converse is formed by interchanging the premise and the conclusion. Thus,
the converse is written as “If you did not receive the proper refund, then you prepared
your own income tax form.”
b. The inverse is formed by negating both the premise and the conclusion. Thus, the in-
verse is written as “If you did not prepare your own income tax form, then you received
the proper refund.”
c. The contrapositive is formed by negating and interchanging the premise and the con-
clusion. Thus, the contrapositive is written as “If you received the proper refund, then
you did not prepare your own income tax form.”
Equivalent Conditionals
We have seen that the conditional p q has three variations: the converse q p, the
inverse p q, and the contrapositive q p. Do any of these “if . . . then . . .”
statements convey the same meaning? In other words, are any of these compound
statements equivalent?
EXAMPLE 3 DETERMINING EQUIVALENT STATEMENTS Determine which (if any)
of the following are equivalent: a conditional p q, the converse q p, the
inverse p q, and the contrapositive q p.
SOLUTION To investigate the possible equivalencies, we must construct a truth table that con-
tains all the statements. Because there are two letters, we need 2
2
4 rows. The
table must have a column for p, one for q, one for the conditional p q, and
one for each variation of the conditional. The truth values of the negations p and
q are readily entered, as shown in Figure 1.56.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 44
Property
Property
Property
the proper refund.”
Property
the proper refund.”
The contrapositive is formed by negating
Property
The contrapositive is formed by negating
clusion. Thus, the contrapositive is written as “If you received the proper refund, then
Property
clusion. Thus, the contrapositive is written as “If you received the proper refund, then
you did not prepare your own income tax form.”
Property
you did not prepare your own income tax form.”
Equivalent Conditionals
Property
Equivalent Conditionals
of
The inverse is formed by negating both the premise and the conclusion. Thus, the in-
of
The inverse is formed by negating both the premise and the conclusion. Thus, the in-
verse is written as “If you did not prepare your own income tax form, then you received
of
verse is written as “If you did not prepare your own income tax form, then you received
the proper refund.”
of
the proper refund.”
The contrapositive is formed by negating
of
The contrapositive is formed by negating
Cengage
the contrapositive of the conditional
Cengage
the contrapositive of the conditional
Rewriting the statement in the standard “if . . . then . . .” form, we have the conditional
Cengage
Rewriting the statement in the standard “if . . . then . . .” form, we have the conditional
“If you prepared your own income tax form, then you did not receive the proper re-
Cengage
“If you prepared your own income tax form, then you did not receive the proper re-
fund.” The converse is formed by interchanging the premise and the conclusion. Thus,
Cengage
fund.” The converse is formed by interchanging the premise and the conclusion. Thus,
the converse is written as “If you did not receive the proper refund, then you prepared
Cengage
the converse is written as “If you did not receive the proper refund, then you prepared
your own income tax form.”
Cengage
your own income tax form.”
The inverse is formed by negating both the premise and the conclusion. Thus, the in-
Cengage
The inverse is formed by negating both the premise and the conclusion. Thus, the in-
verse is written as “If you did not prepare your own income tax form, then you received
Cengage
verse is written as “If you did not prepare your own income tax form, then you received
Learning
, then not
Learning
, then not
p
Learning
p
.
Learning
.
Learning
CREATING VARIATIONS OFACONDITIONAL STATEMENT
Learning
CREATING VARIATIONS OFACONDITIONAL STATEMENT
ou did not receive the proper refund if you prepared your own
Learning
ou did not receive the proper refund if you prepared your own
income tax form,” write the sentence that represents each of the following.
Learning
income tax form,” write the sentence that represents each of the following.
1.4 More on Conditionals 45
pq~p ~qpq q p ~p ~q ~q ~p
TT F F
TF F T
FT T F
FF T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Required columns in the truth table.FIGURE 1.56
An “if . . . then . . .” statement is false only when the premise is true and the
conclusion is false. Consequently, p q is false only when p is T and q is F; enter
an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere in the column under p q.
Likewise, the converse q p is false only when q is T and p is F; enter an F
in row 3 and Ts elsewhere.
In a similar manner, the inverse p q is false only when p is T and q
is F; enter an F in row 3 and Ts elsewhere.
Finally, the contrapositive q p is false only when q is T and p is F;
enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere.
The completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.57. Examining the entries in
Figure 1.57, we can see that the columns under p q and q p are identical;
each has an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. Consequently, a conditional and its con-
trapositive are equivalent:
p q q p.
Likewise, we notice that q p and p q have identical truth values;
each has an F in row 3 and Ts elsewhere. Thus, the converse and the inverse of a
conditional are equivalent:
q p p q.
pq~p ~qpq q p ~p ~q ~q ~p
TT F F T T T T
TF F T F T T F
FT T F T F F T
FF T T T T T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for a conditional and its variations.FIGURE 1.57
We have seen that different “if . . . then . . .” statements can convey the same
meaning—that is, that certain variations of a conditional are equivalent (see Fig-
ure 1.58). For example, the compound statements “If you are compassionate, then
you contribute to charities” and “If you do not contribute to charities, then you are
not compassionate” convey the same meaning. (The second conditional is the con-
trapositive of the first.) Regardless of its specific contents (p, q, p, or q), every
“if . . . then . . .” statement has an equivalent variation formed by negating and in-
terchanging the premise and the conclusion of the given conditional statement.
Equivalent Statements Symbolic Representations
a conditional and its contrapositive ( p q) (~q ~p)
the converse and the inverse (of (q p) (~p ~q)
the conditional p q)
Equivalent “if . . . then . . .” statements.FIGURE 1.58
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 45
Property
Property
Property
Property
FF T T T T T T
Property
FF T T T T T T
Property
3.
Property
3.
4.
Property
4.
Property
FIGURE 1.57
Property
FIGURE 1.57
of
of
TT F F T T T T
of
TT F F T T T T
of
TF F T F T T F
of
TF F T F T T F
FT T F T F F T
of
FT T F T F F T
of
of
of
of
TF F T F T T F
of
TF F T F T T F
Cengage
Figure 1.57, we can see that the columns under
Cengage
Figure 1.57, we can see that the columns under
each has an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. Consequently, a conditional and its con-
Cengage
each has an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. Consequently, a conditional and its con-
trapositive are equivalent:
Cengage
trapositive are equivalent:
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
q
Cengage
q

Cengage

q
Cengage
q
Likewise, we notice that
Cengage
Likewise, we notice that
q
Cengage
q
Cengage
each has an F in row 3 and Ts elsewhere. Thus, the converse and the inverse of a
Cengage
each has an F in row 3 and Ts elsewhere. Thus, the converse and the inverse of a
conditional are equivalent:
Cengage
conditional are equivalent:
q
Cengage
q
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
pq
Cengage
pq
~
Cengage
~
p
Cengage
p
~p~
Cengage
~p~
Cengage
TT F F T T T T
Cengage
TT F F T T T T
TF F T F T T F
Cengage
TF F T F T T F
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
TT F F T T T T
Cengage
TT F F T T T T
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
is false only when
Learning
is false only when
p
Learning
p
Learning
q.
Learning
q.
is false only when
Learning
is false only when
q
Learning
q
is T and
Learning
is T and
q
Learning
q
is false only when
Learning
is false only when
Learning
p
Learning
p
is false only when
Learning
is false only when
enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere.
Learning
enter an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere.
The completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.57. Examining the entries in
Learning
The completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.57. Examining the entries in
Figure 1.57, we can see that the columns under
Learning
Figure 1.57, we can see that the columns under
each has an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. Consequently, a conditional and its con-
Learning
each has an F in row 2 and Ts elsewhere. Consequently, a conditional and its con-
46 CHAPTER 1 Logic
EXAMPLE 4 CREATING A CONTRAPOSITIVE Given the statement “Being a doctor is
necessary for being a surgeon,” express the contrapositive in terms of the
following:
a. a sufficient condition
b. a necessary condition
SOLUTION a. Recalling that a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, we can rephrase
the statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” as follows:
a person is a surgeon, the person is a doctor.”
The premise. A necessary condition is
the conclusion.
Therefore, by negating and interchanging the premise and conclusion, the contraposi-
tive is
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
The negation of The negation of
the conclusion. the premise.
Recalling that a sufficient condition is the premise of a conditional, we can phrase the
contrapositive of the original statement as “Not being a doctor is sufficient for not being
a surgeon.
b. From part (a), the contrapositive of the original statement is the conditional statement
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
The premise of The conclusion of
the contrapositive. the contrapositive.
Because a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, the contrapositive
of the (original) statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” can be
expressed as “Not being a surgeon is necessary for not being a doctor.
The “Only If” Connective
Consider the statement “A prisoner is paroled only if the prisoner obeys the rules.”
What is the premise, and what is the conclusion? Rather than using p and q (which
might bias our investigation), we define
r: A prisoner is paroled.
s: A prisoner obeys the rules.
The given statement is represented by “r only if s.” Now, “r only if s” means that
r can happen only if s happens. In other words, if s does not happen, then r does not
happen, or s r. We have seen that s r is equivalent to r s. Conse-
quently, “r only if s” is equivalent to the conditional r s. The premise of the
statement “Aprisoner is paroled only if the prisoner obeys the rules” is “Aprisoner
is paroled,” and the conclusion is “The prisoner obeys the rules.”
The conditional p q can be phrased “p only if q.” Even though the word if
precedes q, q is not the premise. Whatever follows the connective “only if” is the
conclusion of the conditional.
↑↑
↑↑
notthennotIf
↑↑
↑↑
notthennotIf
↑↑
↑↑
thenIf
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 46
Property
Property
of the (original) statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” can be
Property
of the (original) statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” can be
expressed as “
Property
expressed as “
The “Only If” Connective
Property
The “Only If” Connective
of
the contrapositive.
of
the contrapositive.
Because a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, the contrapositive
of
Because a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, the contrapositive
of the (original) statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” can be
of
of the (original) statement “Being a doctor is necessary for being a surgeon” can be
expressed as “
of
expressed as “
Not being a surgeon is necessary for not being a doctor.
of
Not being a surgeon is necessary for not being a doctor.
Cengage
is the
Cengage
is the
premise
Cengage
premise
contrapositive of the original statement as “
Cengage
contrapositive of the original statement as “
Not being a doctor is sufficient for not being
Cengage
Not being a doctor is sufficient for not being
From part (a), the contrapositive of the original statement is the conditional statement
Cengage
From part (a), the contrapositive of the original statement is the conditional statement
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Cengage
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
The premise of
Cengage
The premise of
the contrapositive.
Cengage
the contrapositive.
Because a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, the contrapositive
Cengage
Because a necessary condition is the conclusion of a conditional, the contrapositive
Cengage
↑↑
Cengage
↑↑
Cengage
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
not
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Cengage
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
not
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Cengage
Learning
Therefore, by negating and interchanging the premise and conclusion, the contraposi-
Learning
Therefore, by negating and interchanging the premise and conclusion, the contraposi-
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Learning
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
The negation of
Learning
The negation of
the premise.
Learning
the premise.
premise
Learning
premise
Learning
↑↑
Learning
↑↑
↑↑
Learning
↑↑
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
not
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Learning
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
not
a person is a doctor, the person is a surgeon.”
Learning
EXAMPLE 5 ANALYZING AN “ONLY IF” STATEMENT For the compound statement
“You receive a federal grant only if your artwork is not obscene,” do the
following:
a. Determine the premise and the conclusion.
b. Rewrite the compound statement in the standard “if . . . then . . .” form.
c. Interpret the conditions that make the statement false.
SOLUTION a. Because the compound statement contains an “only if” connective, the statement that
follows “only if” is the conclusion of the conditional. The premise is “You receive a
federal grant.” The conclusion is “Your artwork is not obscene.”
b. The given compound statement can be rewritten as “If you receive a grant, then your
artwork is not obscene.”
c. First we define the symbols.
p: You receive a federal grant.
q: Your artwork is obscene.
Then the statement has the symbolic representation p q. The truth table for
p q is given in Figure 1.59.
The expression p q is false under the conditions listed in row 1 (when p and
q are both true). Therefore, the statement “You receive a federal grant only if your
artwork is not obscene” is false when an artist does receive a federal grant and the
artist’s artwork is obscene.
The Biconditional p q
What do the words bicycle, binomial, and bilingual have in common? Each word
begins with the prefix bi, meaning “two.” Just as the word bilingual means “two
languages,” the word biconditional means “two conditionals.”
In everyday speech, conditionals often get “hooked together” in a circular
fashion. For instance, someone might say, “If I am rich, then I am happy, and if I
am happy, then I am rich.” Notice that this compound statement is actually the con-
junction (and) of a conditional (if rich, then happy) and its converse (if happy, then
rich). Such a statement is referred to as a biconditional. A biconditional is a state-
ment of the form (p q) (q p) and is symbolized as p q. The symbol p q
is read “p if and only if q” and is frequently abbreviated “p iff q.” A biconditional
is equivalent to the conjunction of two conversely related conditionals:
p q
[(p q) (q p)].
In addition to the phrase “if and only if,” a biconditional can also be ex-
pressed by using “necessary” and “sufficient” terminology. The statement “p is
sufficient for q” can be rephrased as “if p then q” (and symbolized as p q),
whereas the statement “p is necessary for q” can be rephrased as “if q then p” (and
symbolized as q p). Therefore, the biconditional “p if and only if q” can also be
phrased as “p is necessary and sufficient for q.”
EXAMPLE 6 ANALYZING A BICONDITIONAL STATEMENT Express the biconditional
“A citizen is eligible to vote if and only if the citizen is at least eighteen years old”
as the conjunction of two conditionals.
SOLUTION The given biconditional is equivalent to “If a citizen is eligible to vote, then the
citizen is at least eighteen years old, and if a citizen is at least eighteen years old,
then the citizen is eligible to vote.”
1.4 More on Conditionals 47
pq~qp~q
TT F F
TF T T
FT F T
FF T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for the conditional
p q.
FIGURE 1.59
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 47
Property
fashion. For instance, someone might say, “If I am rich, then I am happy, and if I
Property
fashion. For instance, someone might say, “If I am rich, then I am happy, and if I
am happy, then I am rich.” Notice that this compound statement is actually the con-
Property
am happy, then I am rich.” Notice that this compound statement is actually the con-
junction (
Property
junction (
rich). Such a statement is referred to as a biconditional. A
Property
rich). Such a statement is referred to as a biconditional. A
ment of the form (
Property
ment of the form (
of
begins with the prefix
of
begins with the prefix
languages,” the word
of
languages,” the word
In everyday speech, conditionals often get “hooked together” in a circular
of
In everyday speech, conditionals often get “hooked together” in a circular
fashion. For instance, someone might say, “If I am rich, then I am happy, and if I
of
fashion. For instance, someone might say, “If I am rich, then I am happy, and if I
Cengage
artwork is not obscene” is false when an artist
Cengage
artwork is not obscene” is false when an artist
The Biconditional
Cengage
The Biconditional
p
Cengage
p
What do the words
Cengage
What do the words
bicycle, binomial,
Cengage
bicycle, binomial,
begins with the prefix
Cengage
begins with the prefix
languages,” the word
Cengage
languages,” the word
In everyday speech, conditionals often get “hooked together” in a circular
Cengage
In everyday speech, conditionals often get “hooked together” in a circular
Learning
Then the statement has the symbolic representation
Learning
Then the statement has the symbolic representation
p
Learning
p
is false under the conditions listed in row 1 (when
Learning
is false under the conditions listed in row 1 (when
are both true). Therefore, the statement “You receive a federal grant only if your
Learning
are both true). Therefore, the statement “You receive a federal grant only if your
artwork is not obscene” is false when an artist
Learning
artwork is not obscene” is false when an artist
3. p: I watch television.
q: I do my homework.
4. p: He is an artist.
q: He is a conformist.
In Exercises 5–10, form (a) the inverse, (b) the converse, and (c)
the contrapositive of the given conditional.
5. If you pass this mathematics course, then you fulfill a
graduation requirement.
6. If you have the necessary tools, assembly time is less
than thirty minutes.
7. The television set does not work if the electricity is
turned off.
8. You do not win if you do not buy a lottery ticket.
In Exercises 1–2, using the given statements, write the sentence
represented by each of the following.
a. p q b. q p
c. p q d. q p
e. Which of parts (a)–(d) are equivalent? Why?
1. p: She is a police officer.
q: She carries a gun.
2. p: I am a multimillion-dollar lottery winner.
q: I am a world traveler.
In Exercises 3–4, using the given statements, write the sentence
represented by each of the following.
a. p q b. q p
c. p q d. q p
e. Which of parts (a)–(d) are equivalent? Why?
Under what circumstances is the biconditional p q true, and when is it
false? To find the answer, we must construct a truth table. Utilizing the equivalence
p q [(p q) (q p)], we get the completed table shown in Figure 1.60.
(Recall that a conditional is false only when its premise is true and its conclusion
is false and that a conjunction is true only when both components are true.) We can
see that a biconditional is true only when the two components p and q have the
same truth value—that is, when p and q are both true or when p and q are both
false. On the other hand, a biconditional is false when the two components p and q
have opposite truth value—that is, when p is true and q is false or vice versa.
48 CHAPTER 1 Logic
pqpqqp (p q) (q p)
TT T T T
TF F T F
FT T F F
FF T T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for a biconditional p q.FIGURE 1.60
Many theorems in mathematics can be expressed as biconditionals. For
example, when solving a quadratic equation, we have the following: “The equation
ax
2
bx c 0 has exactly one solution if and only if the discriminant
b
2
4ac 0.” Recall that the solutions of a quadratic equation are
This biconditional is equivalent to “If the equation ax
2
bx c 0 has exactly one
solution, then the discriminant b
2
4ac 0, and if the discriminant b
2
4ac 0,
then the equation ax
2
bx c 0 has exactly one solution”—that is, one condi-
tion implies the other.
1.4 Exercises
x
b ; 2b
2
4ac
2a
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 48
Property
In Exercises 1–2, using the given statements, write the sentence
Property
In Exercises 1–2, using the given statements, write the sentence
represented by each of the following.
Property
represented by each of the following.
tion implies the other.
Property
tion implies the other.
Property
xercises
Property
xercises
of
solution, then the discriminant
of
solution, then the discriminant
then the equation
of
then the equation
ax
of
ax
tion implies the other.
of
tion implies the other.
Cengage
Many theorems in mathematics can be expressed as biconditionals. For
Cengage
Many theorems in mathematics can be expressed as biconditionals. For
example, when solving a quadratic equation, we have the following: “The equation
Cengage
example, when solving a quadratic equation, we have the following: “The equation
0 has exactly one solution if and only if the discriminant
Cengage
0 has exactly one solution if and only if the discriminant
0.” Recall that the solutions of a quadratic equation are
Cengage
0.” Recall that the solutions of a quadratic equation are
This biconditional is equivalent to “If the equation
Cengage
This biconditional is equivalent to “If the equation
solution, then the discriminant
Cengage
solution, then the discriminant
Cengage
bx
Cengage
bx
4
Cengage
4
ac
Cengage
ac
Cengage
a
Cengage
a
Learning
Learning
Learning
q.
Learning
q.
Many theorems in mathematics can be expressed as biconditionals. For
Learning
Many theorems in mathematics can be expressed as biconditionals. For
1.4 Exercises 49
9. You are a vegetarian if you do not eat meat.
10. If chemicals are properly disposed of, the environment
is not damaged.
In Exercises 11–14, express the contrapositive of the given
conditional in terms of (a) a sufficient condition and (b) a
necessary condition.
11. Being an orthodontist is sufficient for being a dentist.
12. Being an author is sufficient for being literate.
13. Knowing Morse code is necessary for operating a
telegraph.
14. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
In Exercises 15–20, (a) determine the premise and conclusion,
(b) rewrite the compound statement in the standard “if . . .
then . . .” form, and (c) interpret the conditions that make the
statement false.
15. I take public transportation only if it is convenient.
16. I eat raw fish only if I am in a Japanese restaurant.
17. I buy foreign products only if domestic products are
not available.
18. I ride my bicycle only if it is not raining.
19. You may become a U.S. senator only if you are at least
thirty years old and have been a citizen for nine years.
20. You may become the president of the United States
only if you are at least thirty-five years old and were
born a citizen of the United States.
In Exercises 21–28, express the given biconditional as the
conjunction of two conditionals.
21. You obtain a refund if and only if you have a receipt.
22. We eat at Burger World if and only if Ju Ju’s Kitsch-
Inn is closed.
23. The quadratic equation ax
2
bx c 0 has two dis-
tinct real solutions if and only if b
2
4ac 0.
24. The quadratic equation ax
2
bx c 0 has complex
solutions iff b
2
4ac 0.
25. A polygon is a triangle iff the polygon has three
sides.
26. A triangle is isosceles iff the triangle has two equal
sides.
27. A triangle having a 90° angle is necessary and suffi-
cient for a
2
b
2
c
2
.
28. A triangle having three equal sides is necessary and
sufficient for a triangle having three equal angles.
In Exercises 29–36, translate the two statements into symbolic
form and use truth tables to determine whether the statements are
equivalent.
29. I cannot have surgery if I do not have health insurance.
If I can have surgery, then I do have health insurance.
30. If I am illiterate, I cannot fill out an application form.
I can fill out an application form if I am not illiterate.
31. If you earn less than $12,000 per year, you are eligible
for assistance.
If you are not eligible for assistance, then you earn at
least $12,000 per year.
32. If you earn less than $12,000 per year, you are eligible
for assistance.
If you earn at least $12,000 per year, you are not
eligible for assistance.
33. I watch television only if the program is educational.
I do not watch television if the program is not
educational.
34. I buy seafood only if the seafood is fresh.
If I do not buy seafood, the seafood is not fresh.
35. Being an automobile that is American-made is suffi-
cient for an automobile having hardware that is not
metric.
Being an automobile that is not American-made is
necessary for an automobile having hardware that is
metric.
36. Being an automobile having metric hardware is suffi-
cient for being an automobile that is not American-
made.
Being an automobile not having metric hardware is
necessary for being an automobile that is American-
made.
In Exercises 37–46, write an equivalent variation of the given
conditional.
37. If it is not raining, I walk to work.
38. If it makes a buzzing noise, it is not working properly.
39. It is snowing only if it is cold.
40. You are a criminal only if you do not obey the law.
41. You are not a vegetarian if you eat meat.
42. You are not an artist if you are not creative.
43. All policemen own guns.
44. All college students are sleep deprived.
45. No convicted felon is eligible to vote.
46. No man asks for directions.
In Exercises 47–52, determine which pairs of statements are
equivalent.
47. i. If Proposition 111 passes, freeways are improved.
ii. If Proposition 111 is defeated, freeways are not
improved.
iii. If the freeways are improved, Proposition 111
passes.
iv. If the freeways are not improved, Proposition 111
does not pass.
48. i. If the Giants win, then I am happy.
ii. If I am happy, then the Giants win.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 49
Property
You obtain a refund if and only if you have a receipt.
Property
You obtain a refund if and only if you have a receipt.
We eat at Burger World if and only if Ju Ju’s Kitsch-
Property
We eat at Burger World if and only if Ju Ju’s Kitsch-
The quadratic equation
Property
The quadratic equation
ax
Property
ax
2
Property
2
Property
tinct real solutions if and only if
Property
tinct real solutions if and only if
The quadratic equation
Property
The quadratic equation
solutions iff
Property
solutions iff
b
Property
b
2
Property
2
Property
4
Property
4
ac
Property
ac
A polygon is a triangle iff the polygon has three
Property
A polygon is a triangle iff the polygon has three
of
In Exercises 21–28, express the given biconditional as the
of
In Exercises 21–28, express the given biconditional as the
Cengage
You may become a U.S. senator only if you are at least
Cengage
You may become a U.S. senator only if you are at least
thirty years old and have been a citizen for nine years.
Cengage
thirty years old and have been a citizen for nine years.
You may become the president of the United States
Cengage
You may become the president of the United States
only if you are at least thirty-five years old and were
Cengage
only if you are at least thirty-five years old and were
necessary for an automobile having hardware that is
Cengage
necessary for an automobile having hardware that is
metric.
Cengage
metric.
36.
Cengage
36.
Being an automobile having metric hardware is suffi-
Cengage
Being an automobile having metric hardware is suffi-
cient for being an automobile that is not American-
Cengage
cient for being an automobile that is not American-
made.
Cengage
made.
Learning
I do not watch television if the program is not
Learning
I do not watch television if the program is not
I buy seafood only if the seafood is fresh.
Learning
I buy seafood only if the seafood is fresh.
If I do not buy seafood, the seafood is not fresh.
Learning
If I do not buy seafood, the seafood is not fresh.
Being an automobile that is American-made is suffi-
Learning
Being an automobile that is American-made is suffi-
cient for an automobile having hardware that is not
Learning
cient for an automobile having hardware that is not
metric.
Learning
metric.
Being an automobile that is not American-made is
Learning
Being an automobile that is not American-made is
necessary for an automobile having hardware that is
Learning
necessary for an automobile having hardware that is
metric.
Learning
metric.
Exercises 58–62 refer to the following: Assuming that a movie’s
popularity is measured by its gross box office receipts, six recently
released movies—M, N, O, P, Q, and R—are ranked from most
popular (first) to least popular (sixth). There are no ties. The
ranking is consistent with the following conditions:
O is more popular than R.
If N is more popular than O, then neither Q nor R is more
popular than P.
If O is more popular than N, then neither P nor R is more
popular than Q.
M is more popular than N, or else M is more popular than O,
but not both.
58. Which one of the following could be the ranking of the
movies, from most popular to least popular?
a. N, M, O, R, P, Q
b. P, O, M, Q, N, R
c. Q, P, R, O, M, N
d. O, Q, M, P, N, R
e. P, Q, N, O, R, M
59. If N is the second most popular movie, then which one
of the following could be true?
a. O is more popular than M.
b. Q is more popular than M.
c. R is more popular than M.
d. Q is more popular than P.
e. O is more popular than N.
60. Which one of the following cannot be the most popu-
lar movie?
a. M
b. N
c. O
d. P
e. Q
61. If R is more popular than M, then which one of the fol-
lowing could be true?
a. M is more popular than O.
b. M is more popular than Q.
c. N is more popular than P.
d. N is more popular than O.
e. N is more popular than R.
62. If O is more popular than P and less popular than Q,
then which one of the following could be true?
a. M is more popular than O.
b. N is more popular than M.
c. N is more popular than O.
d. R is more popular than Q.
e. P is more popular than R.
iii. If the Giants lose, then I am unhappy.
iv. If I am unhappy, then the Giants lose.
49. i. I go to church if it is Sunday.
ii. I go to church only if it is Sunday.
iii. If I do not go to church, it is not Sunday.
iv. If it is not Sunday, I do not go to church.
50. i. I am a rebel if I do not have a cause.
ii. I am a rebel only if I do not have a cause.
iii. I am not a rebel if I have a cause.
iv. If I am not a rebel, I have a cause.
51. i. If line 34 is greater than line 29, I use Schedule X.
ii. If I use Schedule X, then line 34 is greater than
line 29.
iii. If I do not use Schedule X, then line 34 is not
greater than line 29.
iv. If line 34 is not greater than line 29, then I do not
use Schedule X.
52. i. If you answer yes to all of the above, then you
complete Part II.
ii. If you answer no to any of the above, then you do
not complete Part II.
iii. If you completed Part II, then you answered yes to
all of the above.
iv. If you did not complete Part II, then you answered
no to at least one of the above.
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
53. What is a contrapositive?
54. What is a converse?
55. What is an inverse?
56. What is a biconditional?
57. How is an “if . . . then . . .” statement related to an
“only if” statement?
THE NEXT LEVEL
If a person wants to pursue an advanced degree
(something beyond a bachelors or four-year
degree), chances are the person must take a stan-
dardized exam to gain admission to a graduate
school or to be admitted into a specific program.
These exams are intended to measure verbal,
quantitative, and analytical skills that have devel-
oped throughout a person’s life. Many classes and
study guides are available to help people prepare
for the exams. The following questions are typical
of those found in the study guides.
50 CHAPTER 1 Logic
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 50
Property
What is a biconditional?
Property
What is a biconditional?
How is an “if . . . then . . .” statement related to an
Property
How is an “if . . . then . . .” statement related to an
“only if” statement?
Property
“only if” statement?
Property
of
Cengage
If N is the second most popular movie, then which one
Cengage
If N is the second most popular movie, then which one
of the following could be true?
Cengage
of the following could be true?
O is more popular than M.
Cengage
O is more popular than M.
b.
Cengage
b.
Q is more popular than M.
Cengage
Q is more popular than M.
c.
Cengage
c.
R is more popular than M.
Cengage
R is more popular than M.
d.
Cengage
d.
Q is more popular than P.
Cengage
Q is more popular than P.
e.
Cengage
e.
60.
Cengage
60.
Learning
Which one of the following could be the ranking of the
Learning
Which one of the following could be the ranking of the
movies, from most popular to least popular?
Learning
movies, from most popular to least popular?
Q, P, R, O, M, N
Learning
Q, P, R, O, M, N
O, Q, M, P, N, R
Learning
O, Q, M, P, N, R
P, Q, N, O, R, M
Learning
P, Q, N, O, R, M
If N is the second most popular movie, then which one
Learning
If N is the second most popular movie, then which one
of the following could be true?
Learning
of the following could be true?
51
1.5 Analyzing Arguments
Objectives
Identify a tautology
Use a truth table to analyze an argument
Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat told Alice that he was mad (crazy). Alice then asked,
‘And how do you know that you’re mad?’ ‘To begin with,’ said the cat, ‘a dog’s
not mad. You grant that?’ ‘I suppose so,’ said Alice. ‘Well, then,’ the cat went on,
‘you see a dog growls when it’s angry, and wags its tail when it’s pleased. Now I
growl when I’m pleased, and wag my tail when I’m angry. Therefore I’m mad!’
Does the Cheshire Cat have a valid deductive argument? Does the conclusion
follow logically from the hypotheses? To answer this question, and others like it,
we will utilize symbolic logic and truth tables to account for all possible combina-
tions of the individual statements as true or false.
Valid Arguments
When someone makes a sequence of statements and draws some conclusion from
them, he or she is presenting an argument. An argument consists of two compo-
nents: the initial statements, or hypotheses, and the final statement, or conclusion.
When presented with an argument, a listener or reader may ask, “Does this person
have a logical argument? Does his or her conclusion necessarily follow from the
given statements?”
An argument is valid if the conclusion of the argument is guaranteed under
its given set of hypotheses. (That is, the conclusion is inescapable in all instances.)
For example, we used Venn diagrams in Section 1.1 to show the argument
“All men are mortal.
Socrates is a man.
the hypotheses
Therefore, Socrates is mortal.” the conclusion
is a valid argument. Given the hypotheses, the conclusion is guaranteed. The term
valid does not mean that all the statements are true but merely that the conclusion
was reached via a proper deductive process. As shown in Example 3 of Section 1.1,
the argument
“All doctors are men.
My mother is a doctor.
the hypotheses
Therefore, my mother is a man.”
the conclusion
is also a valid argument. Even though the conclusion is obviously false, the con-
clusion is guaranteed, given the hypotheses.
The hypotheses in a given logical argument may consist of several interrelated
statements, each containing negations, conjunctions, disjunctions, and conditionals.
By joining all the hypotheses in the form of a conjunction, we can form a single con-
ditional that represents the entire argument. That is, if an argument has n hypotheses
(h
1
, h
2
,...,h
n
) and conclusion c, the argument will have the form “if (h
1
and h
2
...and
h
n
), then c.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 51
Property
its given set of hypotheses. (That is, the conclusion is inescapable in all instances.)
Property
its given set of hypotheses. (That is, the conclusion is inescapable in all instances.)
For example, we used Venn diagrams in Section 1.1 to show the argument
Property
For example, we used Venn diagrams in Section 1.1 to show the argument
of
have a logical argument? Does his or her conclusion necessarily follow from the
of
have a logical argument? Does his or her conclusion necessarily follow from the
given statements?”
of
given statements?”
An argument is
of
An argument is
its given set of hypotheses. (That is, the conclusion is inescapable in all instances.)
of
its given set of hypotheses. (That is, the conclusion is inescapable in all instances.)
Cengage
Valid Arguments
Cengage
Valid Arguments
When someone makes a sequence of statements and draws some conclusion from
Cengage
When someone makes a sequence of statements and draws some conclusion from
them, he or she is presenting an argument. An
Cengage
them, he or she is presenting an argument. An
nents: the initial statements, or hypotheses, and the final statement, or conclusion.
Cengage
nents: the initial statements, or hypotheses, and the final statement, or conclusion.
When presented with an argument, a listener or reader may ask, “Does this person
Cengage
When presented with an argument, a listener or reader may ask, “Does this person
have a logical argument? Does his or her conclusion necessarily follow from the
Cengage
have a logical argument? Does his or her conclusion necessarily follow from the
given statements?”
Cengage
given statements?”
Learning
‘And how do you know that you’re mad?’ ‘To begin with,’ said the cat, ‘a dog’s
Learning
‘And how do you know that you’re mad?’ ‘To begin with,’ said the cat, ‘a dog’s
not mad. You grant that?’ ‘I suppose so,’ said Alice. ‘Well, then,’ the cat went on,
Learning
not mad. You grant that?’ ‘I suppose so,’ said Alice. ‘Well, then,’ the cat went on,
‘you see a dog growls when it’s angry, and wags its tail when it’s pleased. Now
Learning
‘you see a dog growls when it’s angry, and wags its tail when it’s pleased. Now
growl when I’m pleased, and wag my tail when I’m angry. Therefore I’m mad!’
Learning
growl when I’m pleased, and wag my tail when I’m angry. Therefore I’m mad!’
ire Cat have a valid deductive argument? Does the conclusion
Learning
ire Cat have a valid deductive argument? Does the conclusion
follow logically from the hypotheses? To answer this question, and others like it,
Learning
follow logically from the hypotheses? To answer this question, and others like it,
we will utilize symbolic logic and truth tables to account for all possible combina-
Learning
we will utilize symbolic logic and truth tables to account for all possible combina-
tions of the individual statements as true or false.
Learning
tions of the individual statements as true or false.
52 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Using a logical argument, Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat tried to
convince Alice that he was crazy. Was his argument valid?
© Blue Lantern Studio/CORBIS
If the conditional representation of an argument is always true (regardless
of the actual truthfulness of the individual statements), the argument is valid. If
there is at least one instance in which the conditional is false, the argument is
invalid.
EXAMPLE 1 USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT Determine
whether the following argument is valid:
“If he is illiterate, he cannot fill out the application.
He can fill out the application.
Therefore, he is not illiterate.”
SOLUTION First, number the hypotheses and separate them from the conclusion with a line:
1. If he is illiterate, he cannot fill out the application.
2. He can fill out the application.
Therefore, he is not illiterate.
Now use symbols to represent each different component in the statements:
p: He is illiterate.
q: He can fill out the application.
CONDITIONAL REPRESENTATION OF AN ARGUMENT
An argument having n hypotheses h
1
, h
2
,
...
, h
n
and conclusion c can be
represented by the conditional [h
1
h
2
...
h
n
] c.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 52
Property
If the conditional representation of an argument is always true (regardless
Property
If the conditional representation of an argument is always true (regardless
of the actual truthfulness of the individual statements), the argument is valid. If
Property
of the actual truthfulness of the individual statements), the argument is valid. If
there is at least one instance in which the conditional is false, the argument is
Property
there is at least one instance in which the conditional is false, the argument is
invalid.
Property
invalid.
EXAMPLE
Property
EXAMPLE
1
Property
1
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
Property
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
Property
of
If the conditional representation of an argument is always true (regardless
of
If the conditional representation of an argument is always true (regardless
of
represented by the conditional [
of
represented by the conditional [
of
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Using a logical argument, Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat tried to
Cengage
Using a logical argument, Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat tried to
convince Alice that he was crazy. Was his argument valid
Cengage
convince Alice that he was crazy. Was his argument valid
Cengage
CONDITIONAL REPRESENTATION OF AN ARGUMENT
Cengage
CONDITIONAL REPRESENTATION OF AN ARGUMENT
An argument having
Cengage
An argument having
n
Cengage
n
hypotheses
Cengage
hypotheses
represented by the conditional [
Cengage
represented by the conditional [
Cengage
Learning
Learning
Learning
Using a logical argument, Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat tried to
Learning
Using a logical argument, Lewis Carroll’s Cheshire Cat tried to
© Blue Lantern Studio/CORBIS
Learning
© Blue Lantern Studio/CORBIS
We could have defined q as “He cannot fill out the application” (as stated in prem-
ise 1), but it is customary to define the symbols with a positive sense. Symboli-
cally, the argument has the form
1. p q
2. q
the hypotheses
p conclusion
and is represented by the conditional [(p q) q] p. The symbol is read
“therefore.”
To construct a truth table for this conditional, we need 2
2
4 rows. A column
is required for the following: each negation, each hypothesis, the conjunction of
the hypotheses, the conclusion, and the conditional representation of the argument.
The initial setup is shown in Figure 1.61.
Fill in the truth table as follows:
q: A negation has the opposite truth values; enter a T in rows 2 and 4 and an F in
rows 1 and 3.
Hypothesis 1: A conditional is false only when its premise is true and its conclusion
is false; enter an F in row 1 and Ts elsewhere.
1.5 Analyzing Arguments 53
Column Conditional
Representing Representation
Hypothesis Hypothesis All the Conclusion of the
1 2 Hypotheses c Argument
pqqpqq 1
2 p (1
2) c
TT
TF
FT
FF
1.
2.
3.
4.
Required columns in the truth table.FIGURE 1.61
L
ondon—Devotees of writer Lewis
Carroll believe they have found what
inspired his grinning Cheshire Cat,
made famous in his book “Alice’s Ad-
ventures in Wonderland.”
Members of the Lewis Carroll Society
made the discovery over the weekend in
a church at which the author’s father
was once rector in the Yorkshire village
of Croft in northern England.
It is a rough-hewn carving of a cat’s
head smiling near an altar, probably
dating to the 10th century. Seen from
below and from the perspective of a
small boy, all that can be seen is the
grinning mouth.
Carroll’s Alice watched the Cheshire
Cat disappear “ending with the grin,
Featured In
The news
Reprinted with permission from
Reuters.
which remained for some time after the
rest of the head had gone.”
Alice mused: “I have often seen a cat
without a grin, but not a grin without a
cat. It is the most curious thing I have
seen in all my life.”
CHURCH CARVING MAY BE ORIGINAL
‘CHESHIRE CAT
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 53
Property
the hypotheses, the conclusion, and the conditional representation of the argument.
Property
the hypotheses, the conclusion, and the conditional representation of the argument.
The initial setup is shown in Figure 1.61.
Property
The initial setup is shown in Figure 1.61.
Fill in the truth table as follows:
Property
Fill in the truth table as follows:
Property
Property
of
To construct a truth table for this conditional, we need 2
of
To construct a truth table for this conditional, we need 2
is required for the following: each negation, each hypothesis, the conjunction of
of
is required for the following: each negation, each hypothesis, the conjunction of
the hypotheses, the conclusion, and the conditional representation of the argument.
of
the hypotheses, the conclusion, and the conditional representation of the argument.
The initial setup is shown in Figure 1.61.
of
The initial setup is shown in Figure 1.61.
Cengage
ise 1), but it is customary to define the symbols with a positive sense. Symboli-
Cengage
ise 1), but it is customary to define the symbols with a positive sense. Symboli-
cally, the argument has the form
Cengage
cally, the argument has the form
the hypotheses
Cengage
the hypotheses
conclusion
Cengage
conclusion
and is represented by the conditional [(
Cengage
and is represented by the conditional [(
“therefore.”
Cengage
“therefore.”
To construct a truth table for this conditional, we need 2
Cengage
To construct a truth table for this conditional, we need 2
is required for the following: each negation, each hypothesis, the conjunction of
Cengage
is required for the following: each negation, each hypothesis, the conjunction of
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Learning
Learning
Reprinted with permission from
Learning
Reprinted with permission from
Reuters.
Learning
Reuters.
Learning
cannot
Learning
cannot
fill out the application” (as stated in prem-
Learning
fill out the application” (as stated in prem-
ise 1), but it is customary to define the symbols with a positive sense. Symboli-
Learning
ise 1), but it is customary to define the symbols with a positive sense. Symboli-
Learning
Learning
Hypothesis 2: Recopy the q column.
1 2: A conjunction is true only when both components are true; enter a T in row 3
and Fs elsewhere.
Conclusion c: A negation has the opposite truth values; enter an F in rows 1 and 2
and a T in rows 3 and 4.
At this point, all that remains is the final column (see Figure 1.62).
54 CHAPTER 1 Logic
1.
2.
3.
4.
12 c
pqqpqq1
2 p (1
2) c
TT F F T F F
TF T T F F F
FT F T T T T
FF T T F F T
Truth values of the expressions.FIGURE 1.62
12 c
pqqpqq1
2 p (1
2) c
TT F F T F F T
TF T T F F F T
FT F T T T T T
FF T T F F T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for the argument [(p q) q] p.FIGURE 1.63
The last column in the truth table is the conditional that represents the entire
argument. A conditional is false only when its premise is true and its conclusion is
false. The only instance in which the premise (1 2) is true is row 3. Corresponding
to this entry, the conclusion p is also true. Consequently, the conditional (1 2) c
is true in row 3. Because the premise (1 2) is false in rows 1, 2, and 4, the condi-
tional (1 2) c is automatically true in those rows as well. The completed truth
table is shown in Figure 1.63.
The completed truth table shows that the conditional [(p q) q] p
is always true. The conditional represents the argument “If he is illiterate, he
cannot fill out the application. He can fill out the application. Therefore, he is not
illiterate.” Thus, the argument is valid.
Tautologies
A tautology is a statement that is always true. For example, the statement
“(a b)
2
a
2
2ab b
2
is a tautology.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 54
Property
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
Property
TT F F T F F T
Property
TT F F T F F T
Property
TF T T F F F T
Property
TF T T F F F T
Property
FT F T T T T T
Property
FT F T T T T T
Property
2.
Property
2.
3.
Property
3.
4.
Property
4.
Property
Property
Property
Property
pq
Property
pq
Property
TT F F T F F T
Property
TT F F T F F T
Property
Property
TF T T F F F T
Property
TF T T F F F T
Property
Property
of
of
of
of
of
pq
of
pq
of
of
of
of
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
The last column in the truth table is the conditional that represents the entire
Cengage
The last column in the truth table is the conditional that represents the entire
argument. A conditional is false only when its premise is true and its conclusion is
Cengage
argument. A conditional is false only when its premise is true and its conclusion is
false. The only instance in which the premise (1
Cengage
false. The only instance in which the premise (1
p
Cengage
p
is also true. Consequently, the conditional (1
Cengage
is also true. Consequently, the conditional (1
is true in row 3. Because the premise (1
Cengage
is true in row 3. Because the premise (1
is automatically true in those rows as well. The completed truth
Cengage
is automatically true in those rows as well. The completed truth
table is shown in Figure 1.63.
Cengage
table is shown in Figure 1.63.
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
FT F T T T T
Learning
FT F T T T T
FF T T F F T
Learning
FF T T F F T
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
FF T T F F T
Learning
FF T T F F T
Learning
The last column in the truth table is the conditional that represents the entire
Learning
The last column in the truth table is the conditional that represents the entire
EXAMPLE 2 DETERMINING WHETHER A STATEMENT IS A TAUTOLOGY
Determine whether the statement (p q) (p q) is a tautology.
SOLUTION We need to construct a truth table for the statement. Because there are two letters,
the table must have 2
2
4 rows. We need a column for (p q), one for (p q),
and one for (p q) (p q). The completed truth table is shown in Figure 1.64.
1.5 Analyzing Arguments 55
pqpqpq (p q) ( p q)
TT T T T
TF F T T
FT F T T
FF F F T
1.
2.
3.
4.
Truth table for the statement (p q) (p q).FIGURE 1.64
Because (p q) (p q) is always true, it is a tautology.
As we have seen, an argument can be represented by a single conditional. If
this conditional is always true, the argument is valid (and vice versa).
EXAMPLE 3 USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT Determine
whether the following argument is valid:
“If the defendant is innocent, the defendant does not go to jail. The defendant does
not go to jail. Therefore, the defendant is innocent.”
SOLUTION Separating the hypotheses from the conclusion, we have
1. If the defendant is innocent, the defendant does not go to jail.
2. The defendant does not go to jail.
Therefore, the defendant is innocent.
Now we define symbols to represent the various components of the statements:
p: The defendant is innocent.
q: The defendant goes to jail.
Symbolically, the argument has the form
1. p q
2. q
p
and is represented by the conditional [(p q) q] p.
VALIDITY OF AN ARGUMENT
An argument having n hypotheses h
1
, h
2
, . . . , h
n
and conclusion c is valid if
and only if the conditional [h
1
h
2
... h
n
] c is a tautology.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 55
Property
Property
3
Property
3
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
Property
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
whether the following ar
Property
whether the following ar
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
Property
of
of
An argument having
of
An argument having
and only if the conditional [
of
and only if the conditional [
of
Cengage
) is always true, it is a tautology.
Cengage
) is always true, it is a tautology.
As we have seen, an argument can be represented by a single conditional. If
Cengage
As we have seen, an argument can be represented by a single conditional. If
this conditional is always true, the argument is valid (and vice versa).
Cengage
this conditional is always true, the argument is valid (and vice versa).
Cengage
VALIDITY OF AN ARGUMENT
Cengage
VALIDITY OF AN ARGUMENT
An argument having
Cengage
An argument having
and only if the conditional [
Cengage
and only if the conditional [
Cengage
Learning
Learning
Learning
FF F F T
Learning
FF F F T
Learning
Learning
q
Learning
q
)
Learning
)
Learning
(
Learning
(
p
Learning
p
Learning
q
Learning
q
).
Learning
).
) is always true, it is a tautology.
Learning
) is always true, it is a tautology.
Now we construct a truth table with four rows, along with the necessary
columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.65.
56 CHAPTER 1 Logic
Truth table for the argument [(p q) q] p.FIGURE 1.65
1.
2.
3.
4.
21 c
pqqpq 1 2 p (1 2) c
TT F F F T T
TF T T T T T
FT F T F F T
FF T T T F F
The column representing the argument has an F in row 4; therefore, the con-
ditional representation of the argument is not a tautology. In particular, the conclu-
sion does not logically follow the hypotheses when both p and q are false (row 4).
The argument is not valid. Let us interpret the circumstances expressed in row 4,
the row in which the argument breaks down. Both p and q are false—that is, the de-
fendant is guilty and the defendant does not go to jail. Unfortunately, this situation
can occur in the real world; guilty people do not always go to jail! As long as it is
possible for a guilty person to avoid jail, the argument is invalid.
The following argument was presented as Example 6 in Section 1.1. In that
section, we constructed a Venn diagram to show that the argument was in fact
valid. We now show an alternative method; that is, we construct a truth table to de-
termine whether the argument is valid.
EXAMPLE 4 USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT Determine
whether the following argument is valid: “No snake is warm-blooded. All
mammals are warm-blooded. Therefore, snakes are not mammals.”
SOLUTION Separating the hypotheses from the conclusion, we have
1. No snake is warm-blooded.
2. All mammals are warm-blooded.
Therefore, snakes are not mammals.
These statements can be rephrased as follows:
1. If it is a snake, then it is not warm-blooded.
2. If it is a mammal, then it is warm-blooded.
Therefore, if it is a snake, then it is not a mammal.
Now we define symbols to represent the various components of the statements:
p: It is a snake.
q: It is warm-blooded.
r: It is a mammal.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 56
Property
termine whether the argument is valid.
Property
termine whether the argument is valid.
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
Property
USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT
whether the following argument is valid: “No snake is warm-blooded. All
Property
whether the following argument is valid: “No snake is warm-blooded. All
mammals are warm-blooded. Therefore, snakes are not mammals.”
Property
mammals are warm-blooded. Therefore, snakes are not mammals.”
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
Separating the hypotheses from the conclusion, we have
Property
Separating the hypotheses from the conclusion, we have
Property
of
section, we constructed a Venn diagram to show that the argument was in fact
of
section, we constructed a Venn diagram to show that the argument was in fact
valid. We now show an alternative method; that is, we construct a truth table to de-
of
valid. We now show an alternative method; that is, we construct a truth table to de-
termine whether the argument is valid.
of
termine whether the argument is valid.
Cengage
sion does not logically follow the hypotheses when both
Cengage
sion does not logically follow the hypotheses when both
The argument is not valid. Let us interpret the circumstances expressed in row 4,
Cengage
The argument is not valid. Let us interpret the circumstances expressed in row 4,
the row in which the argument breaks down. Both
Cengage
the row in which the argument breaks down. Both
fendant is guilty and the defendant does
Cengage
fendant is guilty and the defendant does
not
Cengage
not
go to jail. Unfortunately, this situation
Cengage
go to jail. Unfortunately, this situation
can occur in the real world; guilty people do not
Cengage
can occur in the real world; guilty people do not
possible for a guilty person to avoid jail, the argument is invalid.
Cengage
possible for a guilty person to avoid jail, the argument is invalid.
The following argument was presented as Example 6 in Section 1.1. In that
Cengage
The following argument was presented as Example 6 in Section 1.1. In that
section, we constructed a Venn diagram to show that the argument was in fact
Cengage
section, we constructed a Venn diagram to show that the argument was in fact
valid. We now show an alternative method; that is, we construct a truth table to de-
Cengage
valid. We now show an alternative method; that is, we construct a truth table to de-
Learning
p.
Learning
p.
Learning
Learning
Learning
The column representing the argument has an F in row 4; therefore, the con-
Learning
The column representing the argument has an F in row 4; therefore, the con-
not
Learning
not
a tautology. In particular, the conclu-
Learning
a tautology. In particular, the conclu-
sion does not logically follow the hypotheses when both
Learning
sion does not logically follow the hypotheses when both
The argument is not valid. Let us interpret the circumstances expressed in row 4,
Learning
The argument is not valid. Let us interpret the circumstances expressed in row 4,
Symbolically, the argument has the form
1. p q
2. r q
p r
and is represented by the conditional [(p q) (r q)] (p r).
Now we construct a truth table with eight rows (2
3
8), along with the nec-
essary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.66.
1.5 Analyzing Arguments 57
12 c
pqrq rpqrq 1 2 p r (1 2) c
TTT F F F T F F T
TTF F T F T F T T
TFT T F T F F F T
TFF T T T T T T T
FTT F F T T T T T
FTF F T T T T T T
FFT T F T F F T T
FFF T T T T T T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
Truth table for the argument [(p q) (r q)] (p r).FIGURE 1.66
The preceding examples contained relatively simple arguments, each con-
sisting of only two hypotheses and two simple statements (letters). In such cases,
many people try to employ “common sense” to confirm the validity of the argu-
ment. For instance, the argument “If it is raining, the streets are wet. It is raining.
Therefore, the streets are wet” is obviously valid. However, it might not be so sim-
ple to determine the validity of an argument that contains several hypotheses and
many simple statements. Indeed, in such cases, the argument’s truth table might
become quite lengthy, as in the next example.
EXAMPLE 5 USING A TRUTH TABLE TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT The following
whimsical argument was written by Lewis Carroll and appeared in his 1896 book
Symbolic Logic:
“No ducks waltz. No officers ever decline to waltz. All my poultry are ducks.
Therefore, my poultry are not officers.”
Construct a truth table to determine whether the argument is valid.
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all T’s.
Consequently, the conditional [(p q) (r q)] (p r) is a tautology;
the argument is valid.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:35 AM Page 57
Property
Property
Property
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all T’s.
Property
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all T’s.
Consequently, the conditional [(
Property
Consequently, the conditional [(
the argument is valid.
Property
the argument is valid.
of
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all T’s.
of
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all T’s.
Consequently, the conditional [(
of
Consequently, the conditional [(
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
FTT F F T T T T T
Cengage
FTT F F T T T T T
Cengage
FTF F T T T T T T
Cengage
FTF F T T T T T T
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
FTT F F T T T T T
Cengage
FTT F F T T T T T
Cengage
FTF F T T T T T T
Cengage
FTF F T T T T T T
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
Cengage
FFT T F T F F T T
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFF T T T T T T T
Cengage
Cengage
Truth table for the argument [(
Cengage
Truth table for the argument [(
Cengage
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
1
Learning
1
Learning
2
Learning
2
p
Learning
p
Learning
Learning
TTT F F F T F F T
Learning
TTT F F F T F F T
Learning
TTF F T F T F T T
Learning
TTF F T F T F T T
Learning
TFT T F T F F F T
Learning
TFT T F T F F F T
Learning
TFF T T T T T T T
Learning
TFF T T T T T T T
FTT F F T T T T T
Learning
FTT F F T T T T T
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
TTT F F F T F F T
Learning
TTT F F F T F F T
Learning
TTF F T F T F T T
Learning
TTF F T F T F T T
Learning
Learning
Learning
TFT T F T F F F T
Learning
TFT T F T F F F T
Learning
Learning
TFF T T T T T T T
Learning
TFF T T T T T T T
FTT F F T T T T T
Learning
FTT F F T T T T T
SOLUTION Separating the hypotheses from the conclusion, we have
1. No ducks waltz.
2. No officers ever decline to waltz.
3. All my poultry are ducks.
Therefore, my poultry are not officers.
These statements can be rephrased as
1. If it is a duck, then it does not waltz.
2. If it is an officer, then it does not decline to waltz.
(Equivalently, “If it is an officer, then it will waltz.”)
3. If it is my poultry, then it is a duck.
Therefore, if it is my poultry, then it is not an officer.
58 CHAPTER 1 Logic
CHARLES LUTWIDGE DODGSON, 1832–1898
T
o those who assume that it is
impossible for a person to
excel both in the creative worlds
of art and literature and in the dis-
ciplined worlds of mathematics
and logic, the life of Charles
Lutwidge Dodgson is a wondrous
counterexample. Known the world over
as Lewis Carroll, Dodgson penned the
nonsensical classics Alice’s Adventures in
Wonderland and Through the Looking
Glass. However, many people are sur-
prised to learn that Dodgson (from age
eighteen to his death) was a permanent
resident at the University at Oxford,
teaching mathematics and logic. And as
if that were not enough, Dodgson is now
recognized as one of the leading portrait
photographers of the Victorian era.
The eldest son in a family of eleven
children, Charles amused his younger
siblings with elaborate games, poems,
stories, and humorous drawings. This
attraction to entertaining children with
fantastic stories manifested itself in much
of his later work as Lewis Carroll. Besides
his obvious interest in telling stories, the
young Dodgson was
also intrigued by
mathematics. At the
age of eight, Charles
asked his father to ex-
plain a book on log-
arithms. When told
that he was too
young to understand,
Charles persisted,
“But please, explain!”
The Dodgson family had a strong ec-
clesiastical tradition; Charles’s father,
great-grandfather, and great-great-grand-
father were all clergymen. Following in
his father’s footsteps, Charles attended
Christ Church, the largest and most cele-
brated of all the Oxford colleges. After
graduating in 1854, Charles remained at
Oxford, accepting the position of mathe-
matical lecturer in 1855. However, ap-
pointment to this position was conditional
upon his taking Holy Orders in the Angli-
can church and upon his remaining celi-
bate. Dodgson complied and was
named a deacon in 1861.
The year 1856 was filled with events
that had lasting effects on Dodgson.
Charles Lutwidge created his pseudonym
by translating his first and middle names
into Latin (Carolus Ludovic), reversing their
order (Ludovic Carolus), and translating
them back into English (Lewis Carroll). In
this same year, Dodgson began his
“hobby” of photography. He is consid-
ered by many to have been an artistic pi-
oneer in this new field (photography was
invented in 1839). Most of Dodgson’s
work consists of portraits that chronicle the
Victorian era, and over 700 photographs
taken by Dodgson have been preserved.
His favorite subjects were children, espe-
cially young girls.
Dodgson’s affinity for children brought
about a meeting in 1856 that would
eventually establish his place in the his-
tory of literature. Early in the year, Dodg-
son met the four children of the dean of
Christ Church: Harry, Lorina, Edith, and
Alice Liddell. He began seeing the chil-
dren on a regular basis, amusing them
with stories and photographing them. Al-
though he had a wonderful relationship
with all four, Alice received his special
attention.
On July 4, 1862, while rowing and
picnicking with Alice and her sisters,
Dodgson entertained the Liddell girls with
a fantastic story of a little girl named Alice
who fell into a rabbit hole. Captivated by
© Bettmann/CORBIS
Historical
Note
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/29/10 3:45 AM Page 58
Property
SOLUTION
Property
SOLUTION
Property
Property
Property
Property
of
of
that had lasting effects on Dodgson.
of
that had lasting effects on Dodgson.
Charles Lutwidge created his pseudonym
of
Charles Lutwidge created his pseudonym
by translating his first and middle names
of
by translating his first and middle names
Cengage
brated of all the Oxford colleges. After
Cengage
brated of all the Oxford colleges. After
graduating in 1854, Charles remained at
Cengage
graduating in 1854, Charles remained at
Oxford, accepting the position of mathe-
Cengage
Oxford, accepting the position of mathe-
matical lecturer in 1855. However, ap-
Cengage
matical lecturer in 1855. However, ap-
pointment to this position was conditional
Cengage
pointment to this position was conditional
upon his taking Holy Orders in the Angli-
Cengage
upon his taking Holy Orders in the Angli-
can church and upon his remaining celi-
Cengage
can church and upon his remaining celi-
bate. Dodgson complied and was
Cengage
bate. Dodgson complied and was
named a deacon in 1861.
Cengage
named a deacon in 1861.
The year 1856 was filled with events
Cengage
The year 1856 was filled with events
that had lasting effects on Dodgson.
Cengage
that had lasting effects on Dodgson.
Charles Lutwidge created his pseudonym
Cengage
Charles Lutwidge created his pseudonym
Learning
Christ Church, the largest and most cele-
Learning
Christ Church, the largest and most cele-
invented in 1839). Most of Dodgson’s
Learning
invented in 1839). Most of Dodgson’s
work consists of portraits that chronicle the
Learning
work consists of portraits that chronicle the
Victorian era, and over 700 photographs
Learning
Victorian era, and over 700 photographs
taken by Dodgson have been preserved.
Learning
taken by Dodgson have been preserved.
His favorite subjects were children, espe-
Learning
His favorite subjects were children, espe-
cially young girls.
Learning
cially young girls.
Dodgson’s affinity for children brought
Learning
Dodgson’s affinity for children brought
about a meeting in 1856 that would
Learning
about a meeting in 1856 that would
eventually establish his place in the his-
Learning
eventually establish his place in the his-
tory of literature. Early in the year, Dodg-
Learning
tory of literature. Early in the year, Dodg-
son met the four children of the dean of
Learning
son met the four children of the dean of
Christ Church: Harry, Lorina, Edith, and
Learning
Christ Church: Harry, Lorina, Edith, and
1.5 Analyzing Arguments 59
Young Alice Liddell inspired Lewis Carroll to
write Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland. This
photo is one of the many Carroll took of Alice.
© Bettmann/CORBIS
Carroll’s book The Game of Logic presents the study
of formalized logic in a gamelike fashion. After listing
the “rules of the game” (complete with gameboard
and markers), Carroll captures the reader’s interest
with nonsensical syllogisms.
Brown University Library
the story, Alice Liddell insisted that Dodg-
son write it down for her. He complied,
initially titling it Alice’s Adventure Under-
ground.
Dodgson’s friends subsequently encour-
aged him to publish the manuscript, and in
1865, after editing and inserting new
episodes, Lewis Carroll gave the world
Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland. Al-
though the book appeared to be a whim-
sical excursion into chaotic nonsense,
Dodgson’s masterpiece contained many
exercises in logic and metaphor. The book
was a success, and in 1871, a sequel,
Through the Looking Glass, was printed.
When asked to comment on the meaning
of his writings, Dodgson replied, “I’m very
much afraid I didn’t mean anything but
nonsense! Still, you know, words mean
more than we mean to express when we
use them; so a whole book ought to mean
a great deal more than the writer means.
So, whatever good meanings are in the
book, I’m glad to accept as the meaning
of the book.”
In addition to writing “children’s sto-
ries,” Dodgson wrote numerous mathe-
matics essays and texts, including The
Fifth Book of Euclid Proved Alge-
braically, Formulae of Plane Trigonome-
try, A Guide to the Mathematical Stu-
dent, and Euclid and His Modern Rivals.
In the field of formal logic, Dodgson’s
books The Game of Logic (1887) and
Symbolic Logic (1896) are still used as
sources of inspiration in numerous
schools worldwide.
Now we define symbols to represent the various components of the statements:
p: It is a duck.
q: It will waltz.
r: It is an officer.
s: It is my poultry.
Symbolically, the argument has the form
1. p q
2. r q
3. s p
s r
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:36 AM Page 59
Property
Property
Property
Property
of
of
Symbolic Logic
of
Symbolic Logic
sources of inspiration in numerous
of
sources of inspiration in numerous
schools worldwide.
of
schools worldwide.
Cengage
In addition to writing “children’s sto-
Cengage
In addition to writing “children’s sto-
ries,” Dodgson wrote numerous mathe-
Cengage
ries,” Dodgson wrote numerous mathe-
matics essays and texts, including
Cengage
matics essays and texts, including
Fifth Book of Euclid Proved Alge-
Cengage
Fifth Book of Euclid Proved Alge-
braically, Formulae of Plane Trigonome-
Cengage
braically, Formulae of Plane Trigonome-
try, A Guide to the Mathematical Stu-
Cengage
try, A Guide to the Mathematical Stu-
Euclid and His Modern Rivals.
Cengage
Euclid and His Modern Rivals.
In the field of formal logic, Dodgson’s
Cengage
In the field of formal logic, Dodgson’s
books
Cengage
books
The Game of Logic
Cengage
The Game of Logic
Symbolic Logic
Cengage
Symbolic Logic
sources of inspiration in numerous
Cengage
sources of inspiration in numerous
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
Learning
a great deal more than the writer means.
Learning
a great deal more than the writer means.
So, whatever good meanings are in the
Learning
So, whatever good meanings are in the
book, I’m glad to accept as the meaning
Learning
book, I’m glad to accept as the meaning
In addition to writing “children’s sto-
Learning
In addition to writing “children’s sto-
1.5 Exercises
60 CHAPTER 1 Logic
In Exercises 1–10, use the given symbols to rewrite the argument
in symbolic form.
1. p: It is raining.
q: The streets are wet.
}
Use these symbols.
1. If it is raining, then the streets are wet.
2. It is raining.
Therefore, the streets are wet.
2. p: I have a college degree.
q: I am lazy.
}
Use these symbols.
1. If I have a college degree, I am not lazy.
2. I do not have a college degree.
Therefore, I am lazy.
3. p: It is Tuesday.
q: The tour group is in Belgium.
}
Use these symbols.
1. If it is Tuesday, then the tour group is in Belgium.
2. The tour group is not in Belgium.
Therefore, it is not Tuesday.
4. p: You are a gambler.
q: You have financial security.
}
Use these symbols.
1. You do not have financial security if you are a
gambler.
2. You do not have financial security.
Therefore, you are a gambler.
123 c
pqr sq rpqrqsp 1 2 3 s r (1 2 3) c
TTTT F F F T T F F T
TTTF F F F T T F T T
TT FT F T F T T F T T
TT F F F T F T T F T T
TFTT T F T F T F F T
TFTF T F T F T F T T
TF FT T T T T T T T T
TF FF T T T T T T T T
FTTT F F T T F F F T
FTTF F F T T T T T T
FTFT F T T T F F T T
FTFF F T T T T T T T
FFTT T F T F F F F T
FFTF T F T F T F T T
FFFT T T T T F F T T
FFFF T T T T T T T T
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
Truth table for the argument [(p q) (r q) (s p)] (s r).FIGURE 1.67
Now we construct a truth table with sixteen rows (2
4
16), along with the neces-
sary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.67.
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all
T’s. Consequently, the conditional [(p q) (r q) (s p)] (s r) is
a tautology; the argument is valid.
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:36 AM Page 60
Property
Property
xercises
Property
xercises
T’s. Consequently, the conditional [(
Property
T’s. Consequently, the conditional [(
a tautology; the argument is valid.
Property
a tautology; the argument is valid.
of
Now we construct a truth table with sixteen rows (2
of
Now we construct a truth table with sixteen rows (2
sary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.67.
of
sary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.67.
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all
of
The last column of the truth table represents the argument and contains all
T’s. Consequently, the conditional [(
of
T’s. Consequently, the conditional [(
Cengage
Cengage
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Cengage
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Cengage
FFTF T F T F T F T T
Cengage
FFTF T F T F T F T T
Cengage
FFFT T T T T F F T T
Cengage
FFFT T T T T F F T T
FFFF T T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFFF T T T T T T T T
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Cengage
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Cengage
FFTF T F T F T F T T
Cengage
FFTF T F T F T F T T
FFFT T T T T F F T T
Cengage
FFFT T T T T F F T T
Cengage
Cengage
Cengage
FFFT T T T T F F T T
Cengage
FFFT T T T T F F T T
FFFF T T T T T T T T
Cengage
FFFF T T T T T T T T
Cengage
Truth table for the argument [(
Cengage
Truth table for the argument [(
p
Cengage
p
Cengage
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
)
Cengage
)
Cengage
Now we construct a truth table with sixteen rows (2
Cengage
Now we construct a truth table with sixteen rows (2
sary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.67.
Cengage
sary columns. The completed table is shown in Figure 1.67.
Learning
Learning
TF FT T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FT T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FF T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FF T T T T T T T T
Learning
FTTT F F T T F F F T
Learning
FTTT F F T T F F F T
Learning
FTTF F F T T T T T T
Learning
FTTF F F T T T T T T
Learning
FTFT F T T T F F T T
Learning
FTFT F T T T F F T T
Learning
FTFF F T T T T T T T
Learning
FTFF F T T T T T T T
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Learning
FFTT T F T F F F F T
Learning
Learning
TF FT T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FT T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FF T T T T T T T T
Learning
TF FF T T T T T T T T
Learning
FTTT F F T T F F F T
Learning
FTTT F F T T F F F T
Learning
Learning
FTTF F F T T T T T T
Learning
FTTF F F T T T T T T
Learning
FTFT F T T T F F T T
Learning
FTFT F T T T F F T T
Learning
FTFF F T T T T T T T
Learning
FTFF F T T T T T T T
17. the argument in Exercise 7
18. the argument in Exercise 8
19. the argument in Exercise 9
20. the argument in Exercise 10
In Exercises 21–42, define the necessary symbols, rewrite
the argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to
determine whether the argument is valid. If the argument is
invalid, interpret the specific circumstances that cause the
argument to be invalid.
21. 1. If the Democrats have a majority, Smith is
appointed and student loans are funded.
2. Smith is appointed or student loans are not funded.
Therefore, the Democrats do not have a majority.
22. 1. If you watch television, you do not read books.
2. If you read books, you are wise.
Therefore, you are not wise if you watch television.
23. 1. If you argue with a police officer, you get a ticket.
2. If you do not break the speed limit, you do not get a
ticket.
Therefore, if you break the speed limit, you argue with
a police officer.
24. 1. If you do not recycle newspapers, you are not an
environmentalist.
2. If you recycle newspapers, you save trees.
Therefore, you are an environmentalist only if you
save trees.
25. 1. All pesticides are harmful to the environment.
2. No fertilizer is a pesticide.
Therefore, no fertilizer is harmful to the environment.
26. 1. No one who can afford health insurance is unem-
ployed.
2. All politicians can afford health insurance.
Therefore, no politician is unemployed.
27. 1. All poets are loners.
2. All loners are taxi drivers.
Therefore, all poets are taxi drivers.
28. 1. All forest rangers are environmentalists.
2. All forest rangers are storytellers.
Therefore, all environmentalists are storytellers.
29. 1. No professor is a millionaire.
2. No millionaire is illiterate.
Therefore, no professor is illiterate.
30. 1. No artist is a lawyer.
2. No lawyer is a musician.
Therefore, no artist is a musician.
31. 1. All lawyers study logic.
2. You study logic only if you are a scholar.
3. You are not a scholar.
Therefore, you are not a lawyer.
5. p: You exercise regularly.
q: You are healthy.
}
Use these symbols.
1. You exercise regularly only if you are healthy.
2. You do not exercise regularly.
Therefore, you are not healthy.
6. p: The senator supports new taxes.
q: The senator is reelected.
}
1. Thesenatorisnotreelectedifshesupportsnewtaxes.
2. The senator does not support new taxes.
Therefore, the senator is reelected.
7. p: A person knows Morse code.
q: A person operates a telegraph.
}
r: A person is Nikola Tesla.
1. Knowing Morse code is necessary for operating a
telegraph.
2. Nikola Tesla knows Morse code.
Therefore, Nikola Tesla operates a telegraph.
HINT: Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as r p.
8. p: A person knows CPR.
q: A person is a paramedic.
r: A person is David Lee Roth.
1. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
2. David Lee Roth is a paramedic.
Therefore, David Lee Roth knows CPR.
HINT: Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as r q.
9. p: It is a monkey.
q: It is an ape.
}
Use these symbols.
r: It is King Kong.
1. Being a monkey is sufficient for not being an ape.
2. King Kong is an ape.
Therefore, King Kong is not a monkey.
10. p: It is warm-blooded.
q: It is a reptile.
}
Use these symbols.
r: It is Godzilla.
1. Being warm-blooded is sufficient for not being a
reptile.
2. Godzilla is not warm-blooded.
Therefore, Godzilla is a reptile.
In Exercises 11–20, use a truth table to determine the validity of
the argument specified. If the argument is invalid, interpret the
specific circumstances that cause it to be invalid.
11. the argument in Exercise 1
12. the argument in Exercise 2
13. the argument in Exercise 3
14. the argument in Exercise 4
15. the argument in Exercise 5
16. the argument in Exercise 6
Use these
symbols.
}
Use these
symbols.
Use these
symbols.
1.5 Exercises 61
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:36 AM Page 61
Property
Use these symbols.
Property
Use these symbols.
1. Being a monkey is sufficient for not being an ape.
Property
1. Being a monkey is sufficient for not being an ape.
Property
2. King Kong is an ape.
Property
2. King Kong is an ape.
Therefore, King Kong is not a monkey.
Property
Therefore, King Kong is not a monkey.
It is warm-blooded.
Property
It is warm-blooded.
It is a reptile.
Property
It is a reptile.
}
Property
}
It is Godzilla.
Property
It is Godzilla.
1. Being warm-blooded is sufficient for not being a
Property
1. Being warm-blooded is sufficient for not being a
of
Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as
of
Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as
Use these symbols.
of
Use these symbols.
Cengage
Cengage
Therefore, if you break the speed limit, you argue with
Cengage
Therefore, if you break the speed limit, you argue with
a police officer.
Cengage
a police officer.
24.
Cengage
24.
1. If you do not recycle newspapers, you are not an
Cengage
1. If you do not recycle newspapers, you are not an
1. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
Cengage
1. Knowing CPR is necessary for being a paramedic.
Cengage
Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as
Cengage
Hypothesis 2 can be symbolized as
r
Cengage
r
Cengage
q
Cengage
q
.
Cengage
.
Learning
Learning
2. Smith is appointed or student loans are not funded.
Learning
2. Smith is appointed or student loans are not funded.
Therefore, the Democrats do not have a majority.
Learning
Therefore, the Democrats do not have a majority.
1. If you watch television, you do not read books.
Learning
1. If you watch television, you do not read books.
Learning
2. If you read books, you are wise.
Learning
2. If you read books, you are wise.
Therefore, you are not wise if you watch television.
Learning
Therefore, you are not wise if you watch television.
1. If you argue with a police officer, you get a ticket.
Learning
1. If you argue with a police officer, you get a ticket.
2. If you do not break the speed limit, you do not get a
Learning
2. If you do not break the speed limit, you do not get a
Learning
ticket.
Learning
ticket.
Therefore, if you break the speed limit, you argue with
Learning
Therefore, if you break the speed limit, you argue with
32. 1. All licensed drivers have insurance.
2. You obey the law if you have insurance.
3. You obey the law.
Therefore, you are a licensed driver.
33. 1. Drinking espresso is sufficient for not sleeping.
2. Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
3. Not eating dessert is sufficient for drinking espresso.
Therefore, not being on a diet is necessary for sleeping.
34. 1. Not being eligible to vote is sufficient for ignoring
politics.
2. Not being a convicted felon is necessary for being
eligible to vote.
3. Ignoring politics is sufficient for being naive.
Therefore, being naive is necessary being a convicted
felon.
35. If the defendant is innocent, he does not go to jail. The
defendant goes to jail. Therefore, the defendant is guilty.
36. If the defendant is innocent, he does not go to jail. The
defendant is guilty. Therefore, the defendant goes to jail.
37. If you are not in a hurry, you eat at Lulu’s Diner. If you
are in a hurry, you do not eat good food. You eat at
Lulu’s. Therefore, you eat good food.
38. If you give me a hamburger today, I pay you tomorrow.
If you are a sensitive person, you give me a hamburger
today. You are not a sensitive person. Therefore, I do
not pay you tomorrow.
39. If you listen to rock and roll, you do not go to heaven. If
you are a moral person, you go to heaven. Therefore,
you are not a moral person if you listen to rock and roll.
40. If you follow the rules, you have no trouble. If you are
not clever, you have trouble. You are clever. Therefore,
you do not follow the rules.
41. The water not being cold is sufficient for going swim-
ming. Having goggles is necessary for going swim-
ming. I have no goggles. Therefore, the water is cold.
42. I wash my car only if the sky is clear. The sky not being
clear is necessary for it to rain. I do not wash my car.
Therefore, it is raining.
The arguments given in Exercises 43–50 were written by Lewis
Carroll and appeared in his 1896 book Symbolic Logic. For each
argument, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the argument in
symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine whether the
argument is valid.
43. 1. All medicine is nasty.
2. Senna is a medicine.
Therefore, senna is nasty.
NOTE: Senna is a laxative extracted from the dried
leaves of cassia plants.
44. 1. All pigs are fat.
2. Nothing that is fed on barley-water is fat.
Therefore, pigs are not fed on barley-water.
62 CHAPTER 1 Logic
45. 1. Nothing intelligible ever puzzles me.
2. Logic puzzles me.
Therefore, logic is unintelligible.
46. 1. No misers are unselfish.
2. None but misers save eggshells.
Therefore, no unselfish people save eggshells.
47. 1. No Frenchmen like plum pudding.
2. All Englishmen like plum pudding.
Therefore, Englishmen are not Frenchmen.
48. 1. A prudent man shuns hyenas.
2. No banker is imprudent.
Therefore, no banker fails to shun hyenas.
49. 1. All wasps are unfriendly.
2. No puppies are unfriendly.
Therefore, puppies are not wasps.
50. 1. Improbable stories are not easily believed.
2. None of his stories are probable.
Therefore, none of his stories are easily believed.
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
51. What is a tautology?
52. What is the conditional representation of an argument?
53. Find a “logical” argument in a newspaper article, an
advertisement, or elsewhere in the media. Analyze that
argument and discuss the implications.
History Questions
54. What was Charles Dodgson’s pseudonym? How did he
get it? What classic “children’s stories” did he write?
55. What did Charles Dodgson contribute to the study of
formal logic?
56. Charles Dodgson was a pioneer in what artistic field?
57. Who was Alice Liddell?
Web project
58. Write a research paper on any historical topic referred
to in this chapter or a related topic. Below is a partial
list of topics.
Aristotle
George Boole
Augustus De Morgan
Charles Dodgson/Lewis Carroll
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
Some useful links for this web project are listed on the
text web site: www.cengage.com/math/johnson
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:36 AM Page 62
Property
If you follow the rules, you have no trouble. If you are
Property
If you follow the rules, you have no trouble. If you are
not clever, you have trouble. You are clever. Therefore,
Property
not clever, you have trouble. You are clever. Therefore,
The water not being cold is sufficient for going swim-
Property
The water not being cold is sufficient for going swim-
ming. Having goggles is necessary for going swim-
Property
ming. Having goggles is necessary for going swim-
ming. I have no goggles. Therefore, the water is cold.
Property
ming. I have no goggles. Therefore, the water is cold.
I wash my car only if the sky is clear. The sky not being
Property
I wash my car only if the sky is clear. The sky not being
clear is necessary for it to rain. I do not wash my car.
Property
clear is necessary for it to rain. I do not wash my car.
Therefore, it is raining.
Property
Therefore, it is raining.
of
you are a moral person, you go to heaven. Therefore,
of
you are a moral person, you go to heaven. Therefore,
you are not a moral person if you listen to rock and roll.
of
you are not a moral person if you listen to rock and roll.
If you follow the rules, you have no trouble. If you are
of
If you follow the rules, you have no trouble. If you are
not clever, you have trouble. You are clever. Therefore,
of
not clever, you have trouble. You are clever. Therefore,
Cengage
If you listen to rock and roll, you do not go to heaven. If
Cengage
If you listen to rock and roll, you do not go to heaven. If
you are a moral person, you go to heaven. Therefore,
Cengage
you are a moral person, you go to heaven. Therefore,
Cengage
Therefore, none of his stories are easily believed.
Cengage
Therefore, none of his stories are easily believed.
Answer the following questions using complete
Cengage
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Cengage
sentences and your own words.
Cengage
Concept Questions
Cengage
Concept Questions
51.
Cengage
51.
52.
Cengage
52.
Learning
Learning
Therefore, no banker fails to shun hyenas.
Learning
Therefore, no banker fails to shun hyenas.
1. All wasps are unfriendly.
Learning
1. All wasps are unfriendly.
Learning
2. No puppies are unfriendly.
Learning
2. No puppies are unfriendly.
Therefore, puppies are not wasps.
Learning
Therefore, puppies are not wasps.
1. Improbable stories are not easily believed.
Learning
1. Improbable stories are not easily believed.
Learning
2. None of his stories are probable.
Learning
2. None of his stories are probable.
Therefore, none of his stories are easily believed.
Learning
Therefore, none of his stories are easily believed.
8. 1. Some animals are dangerous.
2. A gun is not an animal.
Therefore, a gun is not dangerous.
9. 1. Some contractors are electricians.
2. All contractors are carpenters.
Therefore, some electricians are carpenters.
10. Solve the following sudoku puzzle.
11. Explain why each of the following is or is not a
statement.
a. The Golden Gate Bridge spans Chesapeake Bay.
b. The capital of Delaware is Dover.
c. Where are you spending your vacation?
d. Hawaii is the best place to spend a vacation.
12. Determine which pairs of statements are negations of
each other.
a. All of the lawyers are ethical.
b. Some of the lawyers are ethical.
c. None of the lawyers is ethical.
d. Some of the lawyers are not ethical.
4
1
6
8
5
2
3
2
7
3
7
4
6
5
7
6
1
8
4
7
3
9
7
2
4
3
7
8
3
REVIEW EXERCISES
1
TERMS
argument
biconditional
compound statement
conclusion
conditional
conjunction
contrapositive
converse
deductive reasoning
disjunction
equivalent expressions
exclusive or
hypothesis
implication
inclusive or
inductive reasoning
invalid argument
inverse
logic
necessary
negation
premise
quantifier
reasoning
statement
sudoku
sufficient
syllogism
tautology
truth table
truth value
valid argument
Venn diagram
1. Classify each argument as deductive or inductive.
a. 1. Hitchcock’s “Psycho” is a suspenseful movie.
2. Hitchcock’s “The Birds” is a suspenseful movie.
Therefore, all Hitchcock movies are suspenseful.
b. 1. All Hitchcock movies are suspenseful.
2. “Psycho” is a Hitchcock movie.
Therefore, “Psycho” is suspenseful.
2. Explain the general rule or pattern used to assign the
given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
letter that fits the pattern.
3. Fill in the blank with what is most likely to be the next
number. Explain the pattern generated by your answer.
1, 6, 11, 4, _____
In Exercises 4–9, construct a Venn diagram to determine the
validity of the given argument.
4. 1. All truck drivers are union members.
2. Rocky is a truck driver.
Therefore, Rocky is a union member.
5. 1. All truck drivers are union members.
2. Rocky is not a truck driver.
Therefore, Rocky is not a union member.
6. 1. All mechanics are engineers.
2. Casey Jones is an engineer.
Therefore, Casey Jones is a mechanic.
7. 1. All mechanics are engineers.
2. Casey Jones is not an engineer.
Therefore, Casey Jones is not a mechanic.
day morning afternoon dusk night
y r f s _____
Chapter Review
63
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/28/10 9:39 PM Page 63
Property
Fill in the blank with what is most likely to be the next
Property
Fill in the blank with what is most likely to be the next
number. Explain the pattern generated by your answer.
Property
number. Explain the pattern generated by your answer.
1, 6, 11, 4, _____
Property
1, 6, 11, 4, _____
In Exercises 4–9, construct a Venn diagram to determine the
Property
In Exercises 4–9, construct a Venn diagram to determine the
validity of the given argument.
Property
validity of the given argument.
1. All truck drivers are union members.
Property
1. All truck drivers are union members.
Property
Property
Property
day morning afternoon dusk night
Property
day morning afternoon dusk night
y r f s _____
Property
y r f s _____
Property
Property
Property
Property
Property
day morning afternoon dusk night
Property
day morning afternoon dusk night
y r f s _____
Property
y r f s _____
Property
of
Explain the general rule or pattern used to assign the
of
Explain the general rule or pattern used to assign the
given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
of
given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
of
day morning afternoon dusk night
of
day morning afternoon dusk night
of
Cengage
1. Some animals are dangerous.
Cengage
1. Some animals are dangerous.
Cengage
2. A gun is not an animal.
Cengage
2. A gun is not an animal.
Therefore, a gun is not dangerous.
Cengage
Therefore, a gun is not dangerous.
9.
Cengage
9.
1. Some contractors are electricians.
Cengage
1. Some contractors are electricians.
Therefore, all Hitchcock movies are suspenseful.
Cengage
Therefore, all Hitchcock movies are suspenseful.
Explain the general rule or pattern used to assign the
Cengage
Explain the general rule or pattern used to assign the
given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
Cengage
given letter to the given word. Fill in the blank with the
Learning
1. Some animals are dangerous.
Learning
1. Some animals are dangerous.
Learning
Learning
Venn diagram
Learning
Venn diagram
Learning
In Exercises 18–25, construct a truth table for the compound
statement.
18. p q 19. p q
20. p q 21. (p q) q
22. q (p r) 23. p (q r)
24. (q p) (r p) 25. (p r) (q r)
In Exercises 26–30, construct a truth table to determine whether
the statements in each pair are equivalent.
26. The car is unreliable or expensive.
If the car is reliable, then it is expensive.
27. If I get a raise, I will buy a new car.
If I do not get a raise, I will not buy a new car.
28. She is a Democrat or she did not vote.
She is not a Democrat and she did vote.
29. The raise is not unjustified and the management
opposes it.
It is not the case that the raise is unjustified or the
management does not oppose it.
30. Walking on the beach is sufficient for not wearing
shoes. Wearing shoes is necessary for not walking on
the beach.
In Exercises 31–38, write a sentence that represents the negation
of each statement.
31. Jesse had a party and nobody came.
32. You do not go to jail if you pay the fine.
33. I am the winner or you are blind.
34. He is unemployed and he did not apply for financial
assistance.
35. The selection procedure has been violated if his
application is ignored.
36. The jackpot is at least $1 million.
37. Drinking espresso is sufficient for not sleeping.
38. Not eating dessert is necessary for being on a diet.
39. Given the statements
p: You are an avid jogger.
q: You are healthy.
write the sentence represented by each of the
following.
a. p q b. q p
c. p q d. q p
e. p q
40. Form (a) the inverse, (b) the converse, and (c) the
contrapositive of the conditional “If he is elected, the
country is in big trouble.”
In Exercises 41 and 42, express the contrapositive of the given
conditional in terms of (a) a sufficient condition, and (b) a
necessary condition.
41. Having a map is sufficient for not being lost.
42. Having syrup is necessary for eating pancakes.
13. Write a sentence that represents the negation of each
statement.
a. His car is not new.
b. Some buildings are earthquake proof.
c. All children eat candy.
d. I never cry in a movie theater.
14. Using the symbolic representations
p: The television program is educational.
q: The television program is controversial.
express the following compound statements in symbolic
form.
a. The television program is educational and contro-
versial.
b. If the television program isn’t controversial, it isn’t
educational.
c. The television program is educational and it isn’t
controversial.
d. The television program isn’t educational or
controversial.
e. Not being controversial is necessary for a television
program to be educational.
f. Being controversial is sufficient for a television
program not to be educational.
15. Using the symbolic representations
p: The advertisement is effective.
q: The advertisement is misleading.
r: The advertisement is outdated.
express the following compound statements in symbolic
form.
a. All misleading advertisements are effective.
b. It is a current, honest, effective advertisement.
c. If an advertisement is outdated, it isn’t effective.
d. The advertisement is effective and it isn’t misleading
or outdated.
e. Not being outdated or misleading is necessary for
an advertisement to be effective.
f. Being outdated and misleading is sufficient for an
advertisement not to be effective.
16. Using the symbolic representations
p: It is expensive.
q: It is undesirable.
express the following in words.
a. p q b. q p
c. (p q) d. (p q) (p q)
17. Using the symbolic representations
p: The movie is critically acclaimed.
q: The movie is a box office hit.
r: The movie is available on DVD.
express the following in words.
a. (p q) r b. (p q) r
c. (p q) r d. r (p q)
64 CHAPTER 1 Logic
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:37 AM Page 64
Property
All misleading advertisements are effective.
Property
All misleading advertisements are effective.
It is a current, honest, effective advertisement.
Property
It is a current, honest, effective advertisement.
If an advertisement is outdated, it isn’t effective.
Property
If an advertisement is outdated, it isn’t effective.
The advertisement is effective and it isn’t misleading
Property
The advertisement is effective and it isn’t misleading
Not being outdated or misleading is necessary for
Property
Not being outdated or misleading is necessary for
an advertisement to be effective.
Property
an advertisement to be effective.
Being outdated and misleading is sufficient for an
Property
Being outdated and misleading is sufficient for an
advertisement not to be effective.
Property
advertisement not to be effective.
Using the symbolic representations
Property
Using the symbolic representations
of
express the following compound statements in symbolic
of
express the following compound statements in symbolic
All misleading advertisements are effective.
of
All misleading advertisements are effective.
It is a current, honest, effective advertisement.
of
It is a current, honest, effective advertisement.
Cengage
Walking on the beach is sufficient for not wearing
Cengage
Walking on the beach is sufficient for not wearing
shoes. Wearing shoes is necessary for not walking on
Cengage
shoes. Wearing shoes is necessary for not walking on
the beach.
Cengage
the beach.
In Exercises 31–38, write a sentence that represents the negation
Cengage
In Exercises 31–38, write a sentence that represents the negation
of each statement.
Cengage
of each statement.
31.
Cengage
31.
Jesse had a party and nobody came.
Cengage
Jesse had a party and nobody came.
32.
Cengage
32.
You do not go to jail if you pay the fine.
Cengage
You do not go to jail if you pay the fine.
33.
Cengage
33.
express the following compound statements in symbolic
Cengage
express the following compound statements in symbolic
Learning
If I get a raise, I will buy a new car.
Learning
If I get a raise, I will buy a new car.
If I do not get a raise, I will not buy a new car.
Learning
If I do not get a raise, I will not buy a new car.
She is a Democrat or she did not vote.
Learning
She is a Democrat or she did not vote.
She is not a Democrat and she did vote.
Learning
She is not a Democrat and she did vote.
The raise is not unjustified and the management
Learning
The raise is not unjustified and the management
It is not the case that the raise is unjustified or the
Learning
It is not the case that the raise is unjustified or the
management does not oppose it.
Learning
management does not oppose it.
Walking on the beach is sufficient for not wearing
Learning
Walking on the beach is sufficient for not wearing
shoes. Wearing shoes is necessary for not walking on
Learning
shoes. Wearing shoes is necessary for not walking on
56. 1. Practicing is sufficient for making no mistakes.
2. Making a mistake is necessary for not receiving an
award.
3. You receive an award.
Therefore, you practice.
57. 1. Practicing is sufficient for making no mistakes.
2. Making a mistake is necessary for not receiving an
award.
3. You do not receive an award.
Therefore, you do not practice.
In Exercises 58–66, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
whether the argument is valid.
58. If the defendant is guilty, he goes to jail. The defendant
does not go to jail. Therefore, the defendant is not
guilty.
59. I will go to the concert only if you buy me a ticket.
You bought me a ticket. Therefore, I will go to the
concert.
60. If tuition is raised, students take out loans or drop out.
If students do not take out loans, they drop out.
Students do drop out. Therefore, tuition is raised.
61. If our oil supply is cut off, our economy collapses. If we
go to war, our economy doesn’t collapse. Therefore, if
our oil supply isn’t cut off, we do not go to war.
62. No professor is uneducated. No monkey is educated.
Therefore, no professor is a monkey.
63. No professor is uneducated. No monkey is a professor.
Therefore, no monkey is educated.
64. Vehicles stop if the traffic light is red. There is no
accident if vehicles stop. There is an accident.
Therefore, the traffic light is not red.
65. Not investing money in the stock market is necessary
for invested money to be guaranteed. Invested money
not being guaranteed is sufficient for not retiring at an
early age. Therefore, you retire at an early age only if
your money is not invested in the stock market.
66. Not investing money in the stock market is necessary
for invested money to be guaranteed. Invested money
not being guaranteed is sufficient for not retiring at an
early age. You do not invest in the stock market.
Therefore, you retire at an early age.
Determine the validity of the arguments in Exercises 67 and 68 by
constructing a
a. Venn diagram and a
b. truth table.
c. How do the answers to parts (a) and (b) compare? Why?
67. 1. If you own a hybrid vehicle, then you are an
environmentalist.
2. You are not an environmentalist.
Therefore, you do not own a hybrid vehicle.
In Exercises 43–48, (a) determine the premise and conclusion
and (b) rewrite the compound statement in the standard “if . . .
then . . .” form.
43. The economy improves only if unemployment goes
down.
44. The economy improves if unemployment goes down.
45. No computer is unrepairable.
46. All gemstones are valuable.
47. Being the fourth Thursday in November is sufficient
for the U.S. Post Office to be closed.
48. Having diesel fuel is necessary for the vehicle to
operate.
In Exercises 49 and 50, translate the two statements into symbolic
form and use truth tables to determine whether the statements are
equivalent.
49. If you are allergic to dairy products, you cannot eat
cheese.
If you cannot eat cheese, then you are allergic to dairy
products.
50. You are a fool if you listen to me.
You are not a fool only if you do not listen to me.
51. Which pairs of statements are equivalent?
i. If it is not raining, I ride my bicycle to work.
ii. If I ride my bicycle to work, it is not raining.
iii. If I do not ride my bicycle to work, it is raining.
iv. If it is raining, I do not ride my bicycle to work.
In Exercises 52–57, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
whether the argument is valid.
52. 1. If you do not make your loan payment, your car is
repossessed.
2. Your car is repossessed.
Therefore, you did not make your loan payment.
53. 1. If you do not pay attention, you do not learn the
new method.
2. You do learn the new method.
Therefore, you do pay attention.
54. 1. If you rent DVD, you will not go to the movie
theater.
2. If you go to the movie theater, you pay attention to
the movie.
Therefore, you do not pay attention to the movie if you
rent DVDs.
55. 1. If the Republicans have a majority, Farnsworth is
appointed and no new taxes are imposed.
2. New taxes are imposed.
Therefore, the Republicans do not have a majority or
Farnsworth is not appointed.
Chapter Review 65
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:37 AM Page 65
Property
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
Property
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
1. If you do not make your loan payment, your car is
Property
1. If you do not make your loan payment, your car is
Property
2. Your car is repossessed.
Property
2. Your car is repossessed.
Therefore, you did not make your loan payment.
Property
Therefore, you did not make your loan payment.
1. If you do not pay attention, you do not learn the
Property
1. If you do not pay attention, you do not learn the
new method.
Property
new method.
2. You do learn the new method.
Property
2. You do learn the new method.
of
In Exercises 52–57, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
of
In Exercises 52–57, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
of
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
Cengage
concert.
Cengage
concert.
60.
Cengage
60.
If tuition is raised, students take out loans or drop out.
Cengage
If tuition is raised, students take out loans or drop out.
If students do not take out loans, they drop out.
Cengage
If students do not take out loans, they drop out.
Students do drop out. Therefore, tuition is raised.
Cengage
Students do drop out. Therefore, tuition is raised.
61.
Cengage
61.
If I ride my bicycle to work, it is not raining.
Cengage
If I ride my bicycle to work, it is not raining.
If I do not ride my bicycle to work, it is raining.
Cengage
If I do not ride my bicycle to work, it is raining.
If it is raining, I do not ride my bicycle to work.
Cengage
If it is raining, I do not ride my bicycle to work.
In Exercises 52–57, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
Cengage
In Exercises 52–57, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
Learning
In Exercises 58–66, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
Learning
In Exercises 58–66, define the necessary symbols, rewrite the
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
Learning
argument in symbolic form, and use a truth table to determine
whether the argument is valid.
Learning
whether the argument is valid.
If the defendant is guilty, he goes to jail. The defendant
Learning
If the defendant is guilty, he goes to jail. The defendant
does not go to jail. Therefore, the defendant is not
Learning
does not go to jail. Therefore, the defendant is not
I will go to the concert only if you buy me a ticket.
Learning
I will go to the concert only if you buy me a ticket.
You bought me a ticket. Therefore, I will go to the
Learning
You bought me a ticket. Therefore, I will go to the
concert.
Learning
concert.
71. a. What is a sufficient condition?
b. What is a necessary condition?
72. What is a tautology?
73. When constructing a truth table, how do you determine
how many rows to create?
History Questions
74. What role did the following people play in the
development of formalized logic?
Aristotle
George Boole
Augustus De Morgan
Charles Dodgson
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
68. 1. If you own a hybrid vehicle, then you are an
environmentalist.
2. You are an environmentalist.
Therefore, you own a hybrid vehicle.
Answer the following questions using complete
sentences and your own words.
Concept Questions
69. What is a statement?
70. a. What is a disjunction? Under what conditions is a
disjunction true?
b. What is a conjunction? Under what conditions is a
conjunction true?
c. What is a conditional? Under what conditions is a
conditional true?
d. What is a negation? Under what conditions is a
negation true?
66 CHAPTER 1 Logic
95057_01_ch01_p001-066.qxd 9/27/10 9:37 AM Page 66
Property
of
Cengage
Learning
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
Learning
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz